Donate books to help fund our work. Learn more→

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

Karma of Untruthfulness I
GA 173a

16 December 1916, Dornach

Lecture V

If we were not a society whose task it is to observe all things from the point of view of deeper knowledge, indeed of profound spiritual knowledge, I would obviously now bring to a close the discussions we have been having and which were requested from so many different quarters. If it were a matter of anything other than deeper knowledge, then these discussions would of course have to be suspended until such time as the results of the important events now taking place were available.

It is, I believe, without question that every soul who is earnestly and honestly concerned with the welfare of mankind is awaiting with bated breath the outcome of the next few days. The facts will show whether certain sources from what we have called the periphery, the circumference, are capable of coming to their senses sufficiently. If they are not, then the whole of mankind—in the future, too—will be expected to believe that one fights for peace by turning down and excluding the possibility of a relatively early achievement of peace. If matters go in the direction that various voices in the press seem to assume—though no serious observer would still consider such an assumption—then no one would be obliged even to pretend any longer to believe that there is one jot of sincerity in all those declamations which proclaim peace or even the rights of nations. In the near future the world will have the opportunity to decide with full consciousness whether to see the declamations of the will to peace as wrong and untruthful and yet still continue to find them significant, or whether to turn to the truth.

We, however, do stand on the foundation of deeper knowledge, and so there is no need for us to interrupt our observations. We are seeking for the truth, and truth must be found at all costs. For the truth can never be seriously harmful or work harmfully.

Today I intend to put before your soul certain matters which give us the opportunity to make our judgement justifiable in a number of directions. In no way do I want to influence anyone's standpoint, nor their judgement; for we are concerned with looking the facts of the physical plane, as well as the facts and impulses of the spiritual world, calmly in the eye. Some time ago I said that the question of necessity in world events would have to be scrutinized, even in the face of the most painful happenings. But Anthroposophy will never make us into fatalists, in the sense that we speak of necessities as a fate to which we have to resign ourselves. It is justifiable to ask: Did these painful events have to take place? But even if we feel obliged to answer in the affirmative, there is still no question of bowing down to these necessities in a fatalistic way. I should like to start by illustrating what I mean by a comparison.

Let us suppose that two people are arguing about how good the harvest will be next year in a certain area. The one says: The harvest will depend on the constraints laid down by nature. He lists all the constraints—the weather, and all the other conditions that are more or less independent of the will of man. The other, however, might object: You are right, all that exists; but what we ought to do is look at the practical question of how much of a contribution we ourselves can make. Then it is much less a matter of the weather and other things over which I have no influence; my main concern, then, is that I want to play my part in next year's harvest, so on my section of the land I will sow the best quality seed I can find. Whatever the other factors may be, it is my duty to sow the best possible seed, and I will make every effort to do so. The first man may be a fatalist; the second may not deny the reasons for the fatalism of the first, but he will do his best to sow the best quality seed. In the same way, for every person who desires to be prudent it is a matter, above all, of finding out how he can sow the best possible seed.

Of course, for the spiritual development of mankind the expression ‘to sow the proper seed’ means something vastly more complicated than is the case in the comparison I have just cited. It does not mean the application of a few abstract principles. It means taking the demands of mankind's evolution and recognizing correctly what is needed at the present moment for this evolution of mankind. For whatever next year's weather may be like and whatever other hindrances or unfavourable circumstances may apply, if the second person does not sow good seed the harvest will certainly be bad! So it is most important to recognize that at present the salvation of mankind's development demands certain conditions which, at the moment, by far the greatest portion of mankind is resisting. These are conditions which must be incorporated in human development so that a thriving and healthy development can take place in the future. And it must also be realized that man finds himself at present in a phase of development in which, within certain limits, it is up to him to cope with his mistakes.

In earlier times this was not the case. Before the fifth post-Atlantean period, before at least a large part of earthly mankind had come to the full realization of their freedom, divine spiritual powers intervened in earthly development, and it can be clearly perceived that this intervention by divine spiritual powers was sensed by human beings. Today, what matters is to show mankind how it is possible to reach certain insights and, above all, how to form a healthy judgement which coincides with the conditions demanded for man's development. The fact that there is a resistance to this judgement is one of the deeper causes of the present painful events.

Another question we shall have to consider over the next few days is why human beings did not turn to more spiritual inclinations a century ago. For had they done so today's painful situation would surely not have arisen. Let us postpone this a little longer and come to it perhaps tomorrow or the next day. Above all, let us hold to the knowledge that the painful events have come about chiefly as a result of this rejection of man's links with the spiritual world. Present events might therefore be described as a karma of materialism. But this phrase ‘karma of materialism’ must not be taken as an empty phrase; it must be understood in the right way.

Insights that are so deeply necessary have surfaced only sporadically during the years spanned by our lives—the final decades of the nineteenth and the first decades of the twentieth century. Certainly some insights—and much depends on insights—have been cast amongst mankind. Moreover, the attempt was made to cast them in such a way that a considerable number of people might have been included. But, at the moment, for reasons which will be mentioned later, people are still tremendously resistant to any kind of higher, spiritually grounded insight.

I now want to mention a book which appeared years ago. You might of course say: Many books are published, so why is this one so significant? At most, a book can only give people some theoretical instruction, and the salvation of the world is certainly not going to depend on whether they read it or not. Let me tell you that more is at stake than might be expected if certain ideas and insights are disseminated. Look in your soul once more at what I have told you during the last two or three lectures and you will be able to admit that this is so.

The book I mean was published in America and the author is Brooks Adams. When it appeared all those years ago it seemed to me to be one of the most important manifestations of new human insight. Even though the way it was presented to the world was spoilt by the fact that it included a foreword by ex-President Roosevelt, one of the greatest phrasemongers of today, nevertheless the ideas in this book by Brooks Adams could have brought enlightenment in the widest sense of the word. Another factor to be considered in connection with European cultural life was that the German translation of this book was brought out by a publisher of whom it was known that he serves quite particular spiritual streams, streams which are definitely hostile and detrimental, for instance to our Anthroposophical Movement. This is not what matters, however. What always matters is to have a sense for the fact that it is significant if certain ideas are presented to the world under an appropriate flag of this kind. It is quite different if a book is published by, let us say, the Cotta'sche Verlag, a distinguished publishing house which simply publishes books or, as in the case of the book in question, by a publisher who brings out books which serve the purposes of a particular society. There is a great difference between dealing simply with literature and dealing with certain definite impulses!

What is in this book by Brooks Adams? Let me first unfold only the main ideas which are brought forward, I must say, quite generally and abstractly in the most amateurish way and only in so far as their significance could be recognized in America. Yet it is important to know that a bird such as this flies up from this particular spot. Brooks Adams says in effect: There are in the world various nations who have been developing slowly for long ages. In the development of these peoples it is possible to detect both rise and fall: they are born, they pass through infancy, youth, maturity and old age, and then they perish.

This is, to start with, no profound truth but merely a framework. However, what Brooks Adams then develops in connection with the evolution of these peoples in the way of developmental laws certainly has some significance. It can be observed, he says, that in the period of their youth these peoples necessarily develop two tendencies which belong together. To enter properly into ideas such as these of Brooks Adams we must, of course, distinguish strictly between a people as such and the individual human beings; neither must we confuse the concept of a state with the concept of a people. So, Brooks Adams ascribes certain characteristics to a particular developmental period of a people and he also considers that these characteristics belong together. According to him some peoples, in the period of their youth, have the capacity for imagination, that is the capacity to form mental images which are, in the main, drawn from within. They owe their origin to the productive imagination and not to considerations such as those of what we today call science; they are drawn from the creative inner powers of the human being. This characteristic of creative imagination is, according to Brooks Adams, necessarily connected with another: these peoples are warlike. The two characteristics of creative imagination and a warlike disposition are inseparably linked in these peoples. Brooks Adams considers this to be a natural law in the spiritual life of these peoples. Peoples who are both imaginative and warlike are, as it were, a particular type.

In contrast to those peoples who belong to the imaginative and warlike type there are, says Brooks Adams, peoples who belong to another type. Here, creative imagination is no longer predominant, for it has developed into something we can call sober scientific judgement. Peoples who possess this characteristic of sober scientific judgement are not warlike by nature; they are industrial and commercial. These two characteristics—we are speaking of peoples, not individuals—belong together: the scientific and the commercial (for industry is simply a basis for commerce). Thus, there are peoples who are scientific and commercial, and peoples who are imaginative and warlike.

For the moment I do not want to criticize these ideas but merely mention that an opinion is asserting itself, though in a rather dilettante fashion, which years ago fluttered up, as it were, from American soil: Take care not to believe that the whole of mankind can be measured by the same yardstick! Do not imagine that the same ideals can be set for every nation! Note that consideration can only be given to what is founded in evolution, which means that you cannot expect a people like the Slavs, whose character is imaginative, to be unwarlike! Those of you who read Brooks Adams' book attentively, please note this latter example particularly. Judgement must be based, not on external appearances but on inner values, inner affinities.

The book is superficial if only for the reason that such knowledge, if it is expressed at all, should be expressed on the basis of spiritual insights alone. So long as there is a lack of spiritual insights, judgements about the evolution of mankind—which is of course affected by the working of spiritual powers—cannot but be one-sided. Above all, a great truth is omitted: On the physical plane we stand within the realm of maya regarding events as well as the will of human beings. As soon as maya is treated, not as maya but as reality, we must fall into error. And as soon as we fail to pay proper attention to developments within maya and to what resembles development within maya, we are already treating maya as reality.

If it were not nonsensical it would be very nice, for instance, to live in a season of permanent springtime, to be surrounded forever by blossoming, sprouting, burgeoning life. Why did the creators of the universe not arrange things so that we have sprouting, burgeoning life forever? Why do the beautiful tulips, lilies and roses have to fade and decay? The answer is quite simple: they have to fade and decay so that they can bloom again! In so far as we stand on the physical plane it must be clear to us that the one cannot be without the other—indeed, that the one is there for the sake of the other; and there is profound truth in Goethe's saying that nature created death in order to have much life. Since the physical world is maya there is no balance so long as we are in the physical world; a balancing can only come about if we can raise ourselves from the physical to the spiritual world. However, this balance is different from the balance we would expect so long as we hold the physical world to be a reality. So it is necessary to come to know the laws of maya, and to learn that within maya a balance can never be found, either by man or by any other being, if maya is not interwoven with something which lies outside maya but inside spiritual reality.

So, above all, it is always important to come to know maya as maya, to come to understand what it means when sprouting and burgeoning have to be accompanied by decay. In the case of nature it is easy to admit, since we see before our very eyes the facts we have to recognize. It will be easy to make anyone understand that in the summer and autumn of 1917 the fruits will ripen which were sown in the previous year's sowing season. If bad seeds were sown, then of course bad fruits will be harvested. So we will tend to pay attention to the quality of the seed and not allow ourselves to be so easily deceived by maya, as we are in other areas of human life where matters are rather more obscure.

Someone who points in a similar way, in connection with the life of nations, to the effect a bad sowing has on the quality of the ripening fruit, will immediately be met with prejudices. These may, for instance, be expressed as follows: I might suggest to someone that he should not be surprised at his bad harvest since his seed was poor when it was sown; he might then retort that it was his seed and that I am hurting his feelings by saying bad things about it. But I have no intention of hurting his feelings, for the poor quality of his seed might not be his fault at all. It is not a question of hurting a person's feelings but rather of stating an objective fact. It is not for me a matter of judging the connection between him and his seed-corn; that is his affair and I leave it to him entirely. But to know the objective facts it is necessary to inspect the seed-corn very closely and face up to what is really at the bottom of events. If, in doing so, we can maintain a proper objectivity, this might even be beneficial to the sower. Indeed, the benefit to him might be considerable if we succeed in making clear to him the connection between the harvest and the sowing. What I want to make clear to you is the importance of putting forward the thoughts in the right direction, and of seeking them in the right way.

After this prelude, I now want to go back some way in history. The reasons for this will soon be clear to you. I have already drawn your attention during lectures here to a king of England who played an important part for England in the realm of maya, in relation to religious development: Henry VIII. As you know, he was rather good at getting rid of his wives, of whom he had quite a number. He also had—well—let us say, the pluck to break with the Pope who did not want to dissolve one of his marriages. This refusal by the Pope gave Henry VIII the courage to bring about a new religion for the whole of England, inasmuch as it depended on him. We have spoken about this on another occasion.

During the reign of Henry VIII lived the great and eminent Thomas More. He was a man of sublime spirituality, indeed of a spirituality equal, for instance, to that of another great man, Pico della Mirandola, as well as other eminent personalities of that era. Thomas More was an enlightened spirit, even though, despite his enlightened insight, he became Henry VIII's Lord Chancellor and did not despise Henry himself. I shall prove to you in a moment that he did not despise Henry VIII. He was a spirit whose illuminated instinct enabled him to accept maya as maya. Yet, like Pico della Mirandola, he was also a pious man. He was not pious after the manner of Henry VIII, nor after the manner of the Pope; he was a sincere, earnestly pious man and from his point of view rejected all the impulses and attempts at reformation which were already beginning to flicker during his time.

In a certain respect Thomas More was a faithful son of the Catholic church; and although Henry VIII, whose Lord Chancellor he already was, would have loaded him with every honour if he had complied with his wishes, he remained disinclined to turn to a new religion simply because Henry desired to take a new wife. For this he was not only deprived of his position, he was condemned to death, and the record of the court proceedings which culminated in his condemnation is extraordinarily interesting and very characteristic of that time. The wording of the sentence which condemned Thomas More to death is quite remarkable.

Most of you know, since it has long been published in secular books, that in Freemasonry the ascent through the various degrees is connected with certain formulations which also include the manner of death awaiting those who fail to keep the secrets of a particular degree. It is stated that under certain circumstances the candidate will have to die a terrible death; for instance, in the case of one of the degrees, his body shall be cut open and his ashes strewn to the four winds of the earth. These things, as I just said, are now the subject of numerous secular writings. Now the sentence passed on Thomas More coincides exactly with the formulation in respect of a particular degree of Freemasonry: he was to be brought from life to death by a most inhuman method. Yet this alone was not enough. His body was to be divided into as many segments as there are compass points and the pieces were to be scattered in all these directions. Part of this sentence was indeed carried out in this very manner.

Consider that this event took place at the beginning of the fifth post-Atlantean period. Thomas More was born in the second half of the fifteenth century and died in the first half of the sixteenth century. We may well ask whether all he did was to refuse the king the oath of supremacy—that is, refuse to recognize that the English church was independent of the Pope and commanded instead by the King of England. Is this really all he did?

Let us now turn to the most important thing he did, namely something which, even today, can have the utmost significance for anyone who looks at it squarely. Thomas More wrote the book Utopia. On the Best Form of the State and the New Island of Utopia. The main part of this book deals with the institutions of the island of Utopia, which means ‘not place’, or ‘no place’. If we take the book in the sense intended by Thomas More, we discover that Utopia means much more to him than some imaginary land in the external physical world. We should not be so foolish, however, as to assume that More wrote the book simply as an imaginary story. Thomas More cannot be counted among the Utopians. He did not want to present people with some imaginary tale; he wanted to say far more than this, in so far as this was possible in his day.

The main part of the book deals with Utopia, but it also has a very detailed introduction. This explains to us why More wrote the book. There is an important passage I want to bring to your attention, so that you can see that he did not despise Henry VIII. It begins as follows:

‘There was recently a rather serious difference of opinion between that great expert in the art of government, His Invincible Majesty, King Henry the Eighth of England, and His Serene Highness, Prince Charles of Castile. His Majesty sent me to Flanders to discuss and settle the matter.’

While in Flanders as an ambassador for Henry VIII, whom he calls an enlightened and great king, he meets a man he regards as exceptionally intelligent—spiritually, exceptionally important. So he asks him: Since you know so much and can assess matters so correctly, why do you not place your insights at the disposal of some prince? For More considers that most people in the service of princes are not very inspired, and that much that is good and favourable could ensue for the world if such inspired people were to place themselves at the service of the princes. The other now replies: It would be to no avail, for were I to express my views within some ministry or other, I should render the others no cleverer; instead they would very soon throw me out. In order to stress that this man, with whom he himself cannot agree, did actually exist, Thomas More adds: I met this man in the most varied company and he told us how he had once attempted to put forward his views in another company.

This is not merely an introduction to Utopia; Thomas More means something further. We have the curious situation in which Thomas More wishes to express criticism of the England of that time, the England of the turn of the fifteenth to the sixteenth century; the Lord Chancellor wants to criticize England. It goes without saying that someone who thinks as Thomas More does would not embark on a criticism of something abstract. In speaking of England he knows that the English people are not identical with what is meant by the configuration of the English state. He knows this very well and he also knows that the state is not something abstract but that it is made by individuals, and that the English people are not included in any criticism that might be expressed about the actions of these individuals on whom all the more important aspects of the English state depend. So Thomas More seizes on the best possible starting point for a concrete discussion, for it is certainly not concrete, but mere nonsense, to say: England is like this, Germany like that, Italy like the other—and so on; to say this is to say nothing at all.

Now, within the framework of a larger company, More brings this intelligent, enlightened man into contact with someone who is an excellent lawyer, someone whom the world considers to be ‘an excellent lawyer’, and so these two—the intelligent man and the excellent lawyer in the eyes of the world—enter into a discussion of English jurisprudence. English jurisprudence was then of course not as it is today, but no matter: the fifth post-Atlantean period was just beginning. The intelligent and enlightened man thought that it was extraordinarily stupid to proceed against thieves in the way considered proper in the England of that time. This man, who has seen Utopia and later describes it, thought that the whole way in which robbery and other matters were considered was not at all clever. He thought that the deeper reasons for such behaviour should be investigated. Thus he came to reject all the views of that time concerning people's attitude to thieves. The excellent lawyer, of course, could not understand him at all. Let us now occupy ourselves a little with the arguments of the intelligent man—not those of the excellent lawyer. He says:

‘I once happened to be dining with the Cardinal when a certain English lawyer was there. I forget how the subject came up, but he was speaking with great enthusiasm about the stern measures that were then being taken against thieves. “We're hanging them all over the place,” he said, “I've seen as many as twenty on a single gallows. And that's what I find so odd. Considering how few of them get away with it, why are we still plagued with so many robbers?” “What's odd about it?” I asked—for I never hesitated to speak freely in front of the Cardinal.’

Now let us hear the intelligent man speak!

‘ “This method of dealing with thieves is both unjust and socially undesirable: As a punishment it's too severe, and as a deterrent it's quite ineffective. Petty larceny isn't bad enough to deserve the death penalty, and no penalty on earth will stop people from stealing, if it's their only way of getting food. In this respect you English, like most other nations, remind me of incompetent schoolmasters, who prefer caning their pupils to teaching them. Instead of inflicting these horrible punishments, it would be far more to the point to provide everyone with some means of livelihood, so that nobody's under the frightful necessity of becoming a thief and then a corpse.” “There's adequate provision for that already,” replied the lawyer. “There are plenty of trades open to them. There's always work on the land. They could easily earn an honest living if they wanted to, but they deliberately choose to be criminals.” “You can't get out of it like that”, I said.’

This is the intelligent man once again.

‘ “Let's ignore, for the sake of argument, the case of the disabled soldier, who has lost a limb in the service of King and Country, either at home or abroad—perhaps in that battle with the Cornish rebels, or perhaps during the fighting in France, not so long ago. When he comes home, he finds he's physically incapable of practising his former trade, and too old to learn a new one. But as I say, let's forget about him, since war is only an intermittent phenomenon. Let's stick to the type of thing that happens every day.

Well, first of all there are lots of noblemen who live like drones on the labour of other people, in other words, of their tenants, and keep bleeding them white by constantly raising their rents. For that's their only idea of practical economy—otherwise they'd soon be ruined by their extravagance. But not content with remaining idle themselves, they take round with them vast numbers of equally idle retainers, who have never been taught any method of earning a living.

The moment their master dies, or they themselves fall ill, they're promptly given the sack—for these noblemen are far more sympathetic towards idleness than illness, and their heirs often can't afford to keep up such large establishments.

Now a sacked retainer is apt to get violently hungry, if he doesn't resort to violence. For what's the alternative? He can, of course, wander around until his clothes and his body are both worn out, and he's nothing but a mass of rags and sores. But in that state no gentleman will condescend to employ him, and no farmer can risk doing so—for who could be less likely to serve a poor man faithfully, sweating away with mattock and hoe for a beggarly wage and barely adequate diet, than a man who has been brought up in the lap of luxury, and is used to swaggering about in military uniform, looking down his nose at everyone else in the neighbourhood?”

“But that's exactly the kind of person we need to encourage,” retorted the lawyer. “In wartime he forms the backbone of the army, simply because he has more spirit and self-respect than an ordinary tradesman or farm-hand.”

“You might as well say,” I answered,’

Now the intelligent man speaks again.

‘ “that for the purposes of war you have to encourage theft. Well, you'll certainly never run short of thieves, so long as you have people like that about. And, of course, you're perfectly right thieves do make quite efficient soldiers, and soldiers make quite enterprising thieves. The two professions have a good deal in common. However, the trouble is not confined to England, although you've got it pretty badly. It's practically a world-wide epidemic.

France, for instance, is suffering from an even more virulent form of it. There the whole country is overrun even in peacetime—if you can call it that—by mercenaries who have been brought in for much the same reasons as you gave for supporting idle retainers. You see, the experts decided, in the interests of public safety, that they must have a powerful standing army, consisting mostly of veterans—for they put so little faith in raw recruits that they deliberately start wars to give their soldiers practice, and make them cut throats just to keep their hands in, as Sallust rather nicely puts it.

So France has learnt by bitter experience how dangerous it is to keep these savage pets, but there are plenty of similar object-lessons in the history of Rome, Carthage, Syria, and many other countries. Again and again standing armies have seized some opportunity of overthrowing the government that employed them, devastating its territory, and destroying its towns. And yet it's quite unnecessary. That's obvious enough from the fact that for all their intensive military training the French can't often claim to have beaten your wartime conscripts—I won't put it more strongly than that, for fear of seeming to flatter present company.” ’

Thus says the Lord Chancellor, Thomas More. We need hardly do more than copy down what he said then about the poor people of France. You could use these words to formulate the most beautiful sentences to present to the English ministers so that they can fulminate againt ‘Prussian militarism’. But these things were said at the beginning of the fifth post-Atlantean period, and possibly the juxtaposition of today's chatter with what lay at the beginning of it all might cause hurt feelings in some quarters.

You see, Thomas More lets us listen to the words of a person who endeavours to get to the bottom of things, and, moreover, in a way which could be disagreeable to some, even if matters are only touched upon quite superficially. He continues:

‘ “In any case I don't see how it can possibly be in the public interest to prepare for a war, which you needn't have unless you want to, by maintaining innumerable disturbers of the peace—when peace is so infinitely more important.

But that's not the only thing that compels people to steal. There are other factors at work which must, I think, be peculiar to your country.” ’

Thus speaks the man who has come back from Utopia.

‘ “And what are they?” asked the Cardinal.’

A new participant in the conversation.

‘ “Sheep,” I told him. “These placid creatures, which used to require so little food, have now apparently developed a raging appetite, and turned into man-eaters. Fields, houses, towns, everything goes down their throats. To put it more plainly, in those parts of the kingdom where the finest, and so the most expensive wool is produced, the nobles and gentlemen, not to mention several saintly abbots, have grown dissatisfied with the income that their predecessors got out of their estates. They're no longer content to lead lazy, comfortable lives, which do no good to society—they must actively do it harm, by enclosing all the land they can for pasture, and leaving none for cultivation. They're even tearing down houses and demolishing whole towns—except, of course, for the churches, which they preserve for use as sheepfolds. As though they didn't waste enough of your soil already on their coverts and game-preserves, these kind souls have started destroying all traces of human habitation, and turning every scrap of farmland into a wilderness. So what happens? Each greedy individual preys on his native land like a malignant growth, absorbing field after field, and enclosing thousands of acres with a single fence. Result—hundreds of farmers are evicted. They're either cheated or bullied into giving up their property, or systematically ill-treated until they're finally forced to sell. Whichever way it's done, out the poor creatures have to go, men and women, husbands and wives, widows and orphans, mothers and tiny children, together with all their employees—whose great numbers are not a sign of wealth, but simply of the fact that you can't run a farm without plenty of manpower. Out they have to go from their homes that they know so well, and they can't find anywhere else to live. Their whole stock of furniture wouldn't fetch much of a price, even if they could afford to wait for a suitable offer. But they can't, so they get very little indeed for it. By the time they've been wandering around for a bit, this little is all used up, and then what can they do but steal—and be very properly hanged?

Of course, they can always become tramps and beggars, but even then they're liable to be arrested as vagrants, and put in prison for being idle—when nobody will give them a job, however much they want one. For farm-work is what they're used to, and where there's no arable land, there's no farm-work to be done. After all, it only takes one shepherd or cowherd to graze animals over an area that would need any amount of labour to make it fit for corn production. For the same reason, corn is much dearer in many districts.

The price of wool has also risen so steeply that your poorer weavers simply can't afford to buy it, which means a lot more people thrown out of work. This is partly due to an epidemic of the rot, which destroyed vast numbers of sheep just after the conversion of arable to pasture land began. It almost looked like a judgement on the landowners for their greed—except that they ought to have caught it instead of the sheep. Not that prices would fall, however many sheep there were, for the sheep market has become, if not strictly a monopoly—for that implies only one seller—then at least an oligopoly. I mean it's almost entirely under the control of a few rich men, who don't need to sell unless they feel like it, and never do feel like it until they can get the price they want.” ’

I need read no further, but simply point out to you that in this book Thomas More, the Lord Chancellor, a man who shares the views of Pico della Mirandola, expresses bitter criticism through the mouth of a person who may indeed be fictitious and who has been in Utopia; but the criticism is levelled at something that really happened at that time. For indeed over wide areas the people who had tilled the soil with their hands were driven from their land, which was turned into grazing ground for the sheep of the landowners who sought to make profits in this way from the sale of wool.

Thomas More found it necessary to draw attention to the fact that people exist who drive the rural population from the soil they have tilled in order to turn it over to sheep. Those who are able to link effects with causes in an objective way can pursue, on the physical plane, how the structure of the English state today is intimately bound up with what happened all that time ago and was criticized in this way by Thomas More. And if one pursues the matter with the means of the spirit, which also exist, then one discovers that the English people cannot be held responsible for a great deal for which the England of politics must be held responsible. Moreover, those who are responsible for the England of politics are the heirs—in certain cases, even the actual descendants—of those who are criticized here by Thomas More. There is an unbroken evolution which can be traced back to that point. If we take such things into account we shall discover and know that in speeches such as that of Rosebery, which I quoted to you the other day, can be heard the voices of those who long ago made profits from the sale of wool in the manner described. Everywhere the objective connections must be sought. Above all one must be entitled not to be misunderstood in every possible way.

What does it mean when one is reproached and told to be more tactful because, otherwise, the English will think this or that? This is not at all what matters. What is important is that there are certain things in our life today which can be traced back to certain origins, and these origins must be sought in the proper places. There is no cause for anyone, merely because he is English, to rush to defend the impulses of the descendants of those who long ago drove the peasants from house and home, land and soil, in order to keep flocks of sheep instead of retaining arable land. It is necessary to become familiar with the laws of cause and effect, and not babble about one nation or another being to blame for this or that.

Now that I have endeavoured to demonstrate to you a characteristic link between something in the present and something in the past, let me turn to yet another point, in order once again to make a connection. I shall present you with a number of external facts which shall serve the purpose of giving you a foundation on which to build judgements.

A survey of present-day Europe, with the exception of the eastern part which is inhabited by the Slavs, reveals that for the most part it has emerged from what was the kingdom of Charlemagne in the eighth and ninth centuries. I am not concerned at the moment with Charlemagne himself, nor with the fact that there is much argument about him today. This argument about Charlemagne really has as little point as the argument of three sons about their father. If three sons quarrel amongst each other, the reason is frequently that they are all quite right to call a certain person their father. Indeed, three people would often not quarrel amongst each other were it not for the fact that they do all share the same father; and the object of their quarrel as likely as not is their inheritance!

Out of the realm of Charlemagne have come, in the main, three component parts: a western part which, after various vicissitudes, became the France of today; an eastern part which, in the main, has become today's Germany and Austria, with the exception of the Slav and Magyar regions; and a middle part which has become essentially the Italy of today. Strictly speaking, all three are equally justified in tracing themselves back to Charlemagne. Sometimes people even have strange feelings which determine whether they want to be traced back to Charlemagne or not. For instance, when you consider how many Saxons were slaughtered by Charlemagne, it is not surprising if some people attach no particular importance to being traced back to him. So, these three regions emerged from the kingdom of Charlemagne. In order to understand much of what is going on today we need to take into account that throughout the Middle Ages there existed, between the middle and the western region, certain links which were of an ideal nature, links which today no longer exist at all in such areas, apart from some empty phrases which cannot be taken seriously. For the Holy Roman Empire was to a large extent founded on ideals. If you do not wish to believe other sources which speak of these ideals, then read Dante's De Monarchia, or investigate what else Dante thought about these things. Consider, for instance, that it was Dante who reproached Rudolf of Habsburg for taking too little care of Italy, ‘the most beautiful garden in the Empire!’ Dante was, at least during that part of his life that matters most, an ardent adherent of that ideal community which had come into being and was called Germany-Italy.

Then in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries we see that the Venetian Republic began to rebel against what came down from the North. First of all Venice devoured the patriarchate of Aquileia, but the main concern of the Venetians was to gain a foothold on the Adriatic and settle along the coast there. Venice was very successful and we can see how what came from the North was indeed pushed back, particularly by the influence of the Venetian Republic. Then comes the era known as the Renaissance, which flourished in Italy and elswhere, particularly under the influence of the blossoming of the free cities. But this was followed by the Counter-Reformation and the politics emanating from the Pope and Spain, and we see that not until the eighteenth century can Italy begin to think of recovering from centuries of pain and suffering. Since you can read it up in any history book, there is no need for me to describe how the moment at last arrived when Italy found her unity, to the approval of the whole world. Those of us who are familiar with these things know that in German regions just as much enthusiasm was expressed for the unification of Italy as elsewhere.

We might ask how the modern unification of Italy came about. We should look upon the case of Italy as a particularly important example of how unified states come into being. But we must also come to understand the connections between the events in Serbia and Italy which I told you about last week. These are connections which are immensely important for an understanding of the situation today. But first one must consider for a moment how the state of Italy came into being, a state which can surely be recognized ungrudgingly.

We need go back only as far as the Battle of Solferino in which France fought alongside Italy, and where the first step was taken towards the subsequent creation of the modern state of Italy. We are in the fifties of the nineteenth century. How did it come about—for there was a great deal at stake at that time—that the first step on the path towards modern Italy could be taken at Solferino by Italy and France? Read your history books and you will find they fully bear out what I am saying: It came about solely because Prussia and Austria—Austria could only lose—could not reach any agreement!

What happened subsequently is owed to the fact that Italy had in Camillo Cavour a truly great statesman, in whose soul the idea flourished that, from this starting point, something could arise in Italy which would lead to a rebirth of the ancient Roman greatness. But matters took a different turn. Something similar, though perhaps with a very different nuance, occurred; something similar to what we saw in connection with Michael Obrenovich, Prince of Serbia, when he sacrificed his earlier idealistic views to the demands of state necessity. In a similar way the great soul of Camillo Cavour bowed before karmic necessity and made the transition from the ideal to external realism.

I can only give you an outline of these things. Italy proceeded from stage to stage. In the summer of 1871 Victor Emmanuel was able to enter Rome. How had this become possible? It was made possible by Germany's victories over France! From the statesman Francesco Crispi stem the words: Italy went to Rome thanks to the German victories, after France had taken the first initiative at Solferino. But the fact that Rome became the capital of the kingdom of Italy is due to the German victories over France.

Now a remarkable relationship develops between Italy and France. It is interesting to note how to the extent that Italy was able to consolidate her unity, she became at once an opponent and an ally of France. Another factor is that Italy's statesmen set great store by the fact that her state structure was pieced together from the outside and also that she owed to Germany the final great push towards unity. These statesmen also saw that to join forces with France in the way which would have been possible at that time could not be fruitful for her. This stream, however, was in opposition to another, which gained in force from the year 1876 onwards: that of the francophile democratic left-wing party. So now this new state vacillated between an attraction to France which was, I might say, more on the feeling level, and a more practical attraction to Central Europe. The remarkable thing was that in everything that came about at that time it always turned out that the deciding factor was the practical tendency of Central Europe.

A new turn of events came about when France took over Tunisia. It had always been taken for granted that Tunisia would fall to Italy. But now France proceeded to spread herself there. So the practical tendency in Italy began to gain the upper hand, the tendency which leaned towards Central Europe. It is interesting, for instance, that at the Berlin Congress the Italian delegate asked Bismarck, who was quite calmly suggesting that France should spread over into Africa, whether he was really intent on setting Italy and France at each other's throats. Certainly for the Italian statesmen of that time this meant that Italy must turn towards Germany. And since Bismarck had spoken the famous words: ‘The path to Germany lies via Vienna’, Italy had to turn towards Austria too. So the ancient feud, which Austria had taken on as what I would call her tragic destiny, had to be shelved. For everything the Venetian Republic had done meant, basically, that those elements which tended towards Germany had been pushed out of Italy. So Austria had to take on the role of bearing the stream which came down from the North.

As a result of France's actions in North Africa, the francophile stream in Italy had to retreat, and so the connection with Central Europe came to be taken for granted at that time. I am giving you only a sketchy outline of these things since it is, after all, not my task to teach you politics. But it is necessary to know certain things about which, unfortunately, far too little is known these days. Italy joined Central Europe in 1882 in what came to be known as the Triple Alliance. Certain people will always misjudge this Triple Alliance because they cannot accustom themselves to using the valid terms. There really are people who blame the painful events of the present war on the Triple Alliance instead of the so-called Triple Entente, which included the Entente Cordiale. You see, people do not always use the proper terms. Normally you can ask about something which is intended to lead to a particular goal whether it is really getting there and how long it remains valid. Now, it was always said by those who were a party to the Triple Alliance that its purpose was to preserve peace. And it did indeed serve this purpose for many decades; that is, for decades it served the purpose for which its participants said it was intended.

Then came the Triple Entente of which it was also said that its purpose was to preserve peace. Yet within less than a decade peace had disappeared! Anything else in the world would be judged on what it achieves. Yet precisely in this matter people do not condescend to form an objective judgement. Only five years later that secret matter was contrived which gives us the possibility of studying more closely the alchemy of those bullets which were used for the assassination at Sarajevo! The assassination of June 1914 could not possibly fail! For if those bullets had missed their target, others would have succeeded! Every precaution had been taken to ensure that if one attempt failed, the next would succeed. It was better thought out, indeed planned on a larger scale, than any other assassination in the whole of history.

In order to study what our friends have asked us to bring up here, we shall have to discover the alchemy of those bullets. I shall return to this later. For after only five years something had been mingled with the interrelationships of the Triple Entente, something which brought it about that there was a link between every event that took place in Italy and every event that took place in the Balkan countries. The aim was to let nothing happen in the Balkans without a corresponding event in Italy. The passions of the people were to be swayed in such a way that no action could be taken one-sidedly, either in the one country or the other; the people's feelings and thoughts were always to run parallel. For decades there was this intimate connection between the various impulses in the Apennine and the Balkan peninsulas. Sometimes a case of this kind stands out in an extraordinarily symbolic way. It is ‘a beauty’ in the way it conforms exactly to the theory, just as a doctor might find a serious case ‘a beauty’ if it gives him an opportunity of performing a particularly good operation—which does not mean in any way that it is something beautiful in itself.

On a visit to Italy we once called in Rome on a most charming, delightful and friendly gentleman who has since died. He conducted us into his sitting room where we found in a very prominent position the portraits, personally autographed, of Draga Masin and Alexander Obrenovich. This friendly gentleman was not only a famous professor; he was the organizer of the so-called Latin League, which was concerned with the separation of South Tyrol and Trieste from Austria in favour of Italy. Of course I do not want to draw any great conclusions from such an insignificant experience. But it is significant symbolically that somebody who organizes the Latin League—I am not judging or criticizing, merely reporting—and, in connection with this Latin League, causes the students of Innsbruck university to riot, should have in his sitting room, visible to all comers, the autographed portraits of Alexander Obrenovich and Draga Masin. Since the secret threads which link Rome and Belgrade were well known to me at the time, this experience did make an impression on me as being symptomatic in a certain way. Karma does, after all, lead us to whatever is important for us in the world, and if we are capable of seeing and understanding things in the proper way, then we realize that karma has brought us to a point where there is something to be ‘sniffed out’ in the furtherance of our knowledge.

Things now developed in such a way that in 1888, a year in which war could have broken out just as it did in 1914, the crisis was averted because Crispi remained loyal to the Triple Alliance. He remained loyal to the Triple Alliance because France was proceeding to spread herself in North Africa. France embarked at that time on a political tactic aimed at Italy, who was starting to turn away from her. The French themselves said this tactic was intended to bring about the ‘re-conquering of Italy by means of hunger’, that is, a kind of trade war was attempted against Italy, and this trade war certainly played an important role at that time. The consequence was that Italy's practical links with Central Europe were increasingly strengthened. It is perhaps just as well if I give you the opinion of a Frenchman on this, rather than that of a German. He said that modern Italy was economically a German colony.

It has often been stressed, not only by Germans but by others as well, that Italy was saved by her close economic ties with Germany from the danger of being conquered by France through hunger—not a nice prospect. All this contributed to the peaceful settlement of the crisis at the end of the eighties. It is most interesting to study this crisis in all its details. It reveals something quite special to someone who is inclined to take account of interconnections and not be deceived. I did the following: I called to mind the events of 1888 and superimposed on them the date 1914. The events are absolutely identical! Just as in 1914 the incitements in the press were started in Petersburg and then taken up in Germany, so it was in 1888. As then, so also in 1914, a conflict was to be brought about between Germany and Austria. In short, every detail is the same. It is interesting that I have read aloud to various people a speech made in 1888 in which I replaced the date 1888 by 1914. Everybody believed that the speech was made in 1914!

When such things are possible we are not inclined to speak of coincidences. We have to understand that there are driving forces and that these driving forces work in a systematic way. In 1888 the matter was averted in the manner I have described. Then the situation became more complicated. The complication arose particularly because the connection of the Apennine peninsula to Central Europe took on a most peculiar character as far as Italy was concerned. It is psychologically interesting to study these things. It really came to a point where Italy, political Italy, had to be treated like some hysterical ladies are treated. The most unbelievable things developed, particularly because the opinion grew and was propagated in Europe that Austria must break up. I am not criticizing, only reporting.

You may gain an impression of how this opinion was propagated in Europe by reading the publications of Loiseaux, Chéradame and others, all of which treat of the assumption that Austria will be divided up in the near future. Now these judgements of Loiseaux and Chéradame and the others were thrown onto what was smouldering away down in the South. Under these circumstances it was definitely not easy to carry on what is usually known as politics. For instance, Oberdank was much celebrated in Italy. He had attempted to assassinate Emperor Franz Josef. In Vienna, on the other hand, a picture in an exhibition had to be renamed for the visit of the Duke of the Abruzzi. Its title was The Naval Battle of Lissa. This battle had been won by Austria, and so as not to offend the Duke of the Abruzzi the picture had to be renamed Naval Battle. This is just one example among many. I am not criticizing, but I do wonder about the question of give and take. Would anyone in Italy have condescended to be so considerate as to omit the name of a sea battle Italy had won? In Vienna they were. Whether it is right or wrong, it does raise the question of give and take. I mention this in order to characterize the different moods somewhat. For it is these moods which matter when streams such as that of the ‘Grand Orient de France’ come into play and when occult impulses of this kind start to take a hold.

Certain things of which people have taken no note so far will have to become things of which they take a great deal of note in the future, for it is not the case that the ‘Massonieri’, as also other secret brotherhoods, do not notice what is there; rather they set themselves the task of making use of those forces which are indeed there. They know where the forces are of which they must make use. So if on the Apennine peninsula there exists a certain stream, and if on the Balkan peninsula there exists another stream, then suitable use must be made of these two streams so that, at the right moment—that is, the right moment from the point of view of these people—one thing or another can be set in motion.

Let this be a preparation for the alchemical discussion I mentioned, which will take us further along our path. Please note that, in order to meet the wishes of our friends, I cannot but mention a certain amount of what is going on at the present time. What I have to say has to be linked to certain things which do exist, even if not everybody agrees that these should be brought out into the open. I am convinced that one of the chief causes for the painful events going on in the world today is the attitude that a blind eye can be turned to certain matters while others are discussed on the basis of an entirely false premise. Even in the face of large-scale matters of this kind, each individual should start from a foundation of self-knowledge. And a portion of self-knowledge is involved if we recognize that to claim no interest in these things and to want only to hear of occult matters is, in a small way, no different from all that adds up to the events we are experiencing today. For spiritual things are not only those which have to do with higher worlds. These, to start with, are of course occult for everybody. But much of what takes place on the physical plane is also occult for many people. We can only hope that much of what is occult and hidden on this plane may be revealed! For one of the causes of today's misery is that so much remains occult for so many people, who nevertheless persist in forming judgements.

Fünfter Vortrag

Meine lieben Freunde! Wären wir nicht eine Vereinigung, welche alle Dinge vom Gesichtspunkt der Erkenntnis, und zwar der vertieften geistigen Erkenntnis aus, zu betrachten hat, so wäre es selbstverständlich; daß ich gerade mit den von vielen! Seiten gewünschten Betrachtungen, die wir seit einigen Tagen anstellen, jetzt einhalten müßte, denn auf jeder anderen Grundlage als einer ernsthaften und objektiven Erkenntnis - wenn es sich denn um Erkenntnis handeln würde —, müßte selbstverständlich mit diesen Betrachtungen ausgesetzt werden bis zu dem Zeitpunkt, an dem effektive Ergebnisse der wichtigen Vorgänge unserer Tage vorliegen.

Es ist, glaube ich, auch selbstverständlich, daß jede Seele, welche es ernst und aufrichtig mit dem menschlichen Heil meint, in banger Erwartung demjenigen entgegensieht, was in den nächsten Tagen geschieht, muß es sich doch durch die Tatsachen entscheiden, ob gewisse Stimmen aus dem, was wir in diesen Betrachtungen die Peripherie, den Umkreis, genannt haben, in der Lage sind, sich noch so weit auf sich selbst zu besinnen, daß der ganzen Menschheit, auch der Menschheit der Zukunft, eigentlich nicht zugemutet werden dürfte, daran zu glauben, daß man den Frieden für die Menschheit wolle, daß man für den Frieden kämpfe, wenn man die Möglichkeit, diesen Frieden zu erlangen - und zwar in verhältnismäßig kürzester Zeit zu erlangen -, nicht ergreift. Es wäre niemand, nicht einmal dem Scheine nach - dem Scheine nach sage ich - verpflichtet, an ein Quentchen Aufrichtigkeit in all jenen Deklamationen zu glauben, die vom Frieden oder gar vom Recht der Völker sich hören lassen, wenn die Dinge:so verlaufen würden, wie es nach den Zeitungsstimmen sich ausnimmt, die freilich für einen ernsten Beobachter heute nicht mehr in Betracht kommen. Aber die Welt wird ja in der nächsten Zeit Gelegenheit haben, weiteres zu hören, und sie wird sich entschließen müssen, entweder mit vollem Bewußtsein die Deklamationen von einem Willen zum Frieden it unrichtiger, in unwahrhaftiger Weise aufzunehmen und sie weiter noch irgendwie erheblich zu finden oder sich zur Wahrheit zu wenden. Aber wir, meine lieben Freunde, stehen ja eben auf dem Boden der Erkenntnis, und deshalb brauchen wir diese Betrachtungen nicht zu unterbrechen. Wir suchen die Wahrheit, und die Wahrheit muß in allen Fällen das sein, was zu suchen ist. Deshalb kann sie niemals im Ernste schädlich sein oder schädlich wirken.

Ich will Ihnen nun heute einiges vor die Seele führen, was die Möglichkeit bieten kann, in mancher Richtung unser Urteil zu einem berechtigten zu machen. Ich möchte - und das werden Sie aus den verschiedenen Bemerkungen, die ich machte, wohl entnommen haben - nicht im geringsten weder den Standpunkt noch das Urteil von irgend jemandem beeinflussen, aber es handelt sich eben darum, sowohl den Tatsachen des physischen Planes wie den Tatsachen und Impulsen der geistigen Welt ruhig ins Auge zu schauen. Ich habe Ihnen schon vor einiger Zeit davon gesprochen, daß gewiß die Frage der Notwendigkeit im Weltengeschehen ins Auge gefaßt werden muß - selbst gegenüber den schmerzlichsten Ereignissen. Aber Anthroposophie wird uns niemals zu Fatalisten machen, wird uns niemals dazu bringen können, von der Notwendigkeit so zu sprechen, daß wir einfach sagen, man habe sich in diese Notwendigkeiten zu fügen wie in ein Fatum. Man wird die Frage aufwerfen können: Mußten denn diese schmerzlichen Ereignisse kommen, die da gekommen sind? Selbst für den Fall, daß man - es sei als Hypothese angenommen - sich gedrängt fühlen müßte zu sagen: Ja, sie sind notwendig gewesen -, selbst für diesen Fall kann es sich nicht darum handeln, sich einfach fatalistisch in diese Notwendigkeit zu fügen. Was ich damit meine, möchte ich zunächst einmal durch einen Vergleich klarmachen.

Nehmen wir einmal an, zwei Menschen stritten sich darüber, wie es denn auf einem bestimmten Gebiete mit der Ernte des nächsten Jahres sein würde. Nun ja, da könnte jemand kommen und sagen: Diese Ernte hängt von den Naturnotwendigkeiten ab, man hat es mit einer äußeren Notwendigkeit zu tun. - Und er könnte sehr schön alle Notwendigkeiten aufzählen: das Wetter und die sonstigen Bedingungen, die mehr oder weniger von dem menschlichen Willen unabhängig sind. Schön, gut! Der andere könnte aber sagen: Du hast recht, das mag ja alles bestehen, aber es handelt sich vor allen Dingen darum, die Frage soweit praktisch ins Auge zu fassen, als sie unser praktisches Mittun erfordert. Und da kommt es mir eigentlich viel weniger darauf an, jetzt über das Wetter, über diese oder jene Dinge zu sprechen, sondern es kommt mir darauf an, daß ich, der ich beteiligt bin und beteiligt sein will an der Ernte des nächsten Jahres, den besten Samen ausstreue, den ich finden kann. Und wie auch die andern Faktoren sein mögen - es ist an mir, den besten Samen auszustreuen, und ich werde mich bemühen, es zu tun. - Der erste Mann mag Fatalist sein, der zweite wird die Grundlage für seinen Fatalismus nicht ableugnen, aber er wird alles tun, um den rechten Samen auszustreuen. Und so handelt es sich denn auch für jeden Menschen, der einsichtig sein will, vor allen Dingen darum, die Möglichkeit zu finden, den rechten Samen auszustreuen.

Nun bedeutet natürlich für die geistige Entwicklung der Menschheit dieses Wort «den rechten Samen ausstreuen» etwas viel Komplizierteres als für den Vergleich, den ich eben angeführt habe, denn es wird sich darum handeln, nicht bloß ein paar abstrakte Grundsätze geltend zu machen, sondern aus den Bedingungen der Menschheitsentwicklung heraus in richtiger Weise zu erkennen, was für diese Menschheitsentwicklung gerade im gegenwärtigen Zeitpunkte notwendig ist. Wie auch das Wetter des nächsten Jahres sein mag, was auch für Hindernisse oder ungünstige Bedingungen eintreten mögen — wenn der zweite seinen Samen nicht ausstreut, dann wird ganz gewiß keine Ernte kommen, nicht einmal eine schlechte! Und so handelt es sich darum einzusehen, daß in der Gegenwart gewisse Bedingungen zu schaffen notwendig sind, gegen welche sich der größte, der weitaus größte Teil der Menschen heute noch sträubt - Bedingungen, die der Menschheitsentwicklung einverleibt werden müssen, damit eine gedeihliche, heilsame Entwicklung in der Zukunft geschehen könne. Und es handelt sich darum einzusehen, daß vor allen Dingen die Menschheit gegenwärtig in einer solchen Entwicklungsphase ist, daß es ihr innerhalb gewisser Grenzen selbst überlassen ist, mit ihren Irrtümern zurechtzukommen.

Das war in früheren Zeiten nicht so, meine lieben Freunde - in früheren Zeiten bis zu dem fünften nachatlantischen Zeitraum hinauf, als die Erdenmenschen, wenigstens zu einem großen Teil, dazu gebracht wurden, sich ihrer Freiheit völlig bewußt zu werden; vorher griffen göttlich-geistige Mächte direkt in die Erdenentwicklung ein, und sie griffen so ein, daß dieses Eingreifen der göttlich-geistigen Mächte von den Menschen auch empfunden wurde. Das war deutlich wahrzunehmen. Und es kommt heute darauf an, die Menschheit auf die Notwendigkeit hinzuweisen, zu gewissen Einsichten zu kommen, vor allen Dingen dazu zu kommen, über gewisse Dinge ein gesundes, ein mit den Entwicklungsbedingungen der Menschheit zusammenstimmendes Urteil zu haben. Daß ein Sich-Sträuben gegen dieses Urteil vorhanden ist, gehört zu den tieferen Veranlassungen der gegenwärtigen schmerzlichen Ereignisse.

Gewiß, wir werden in diesen Tagen auch über die Frage zu sprechen haben, warum die Menschheit sich nicht vor einem Jahrhundert spirituelleren Tendenzen zugewendet hat, denn hätte sie das getan, so wäre ganz gewiß die heutige schmerzliche Lage nicht eingetreten. Aber diese Frage wollen wir für heute noch ein wenig vertagen und sie uns vielleicht morgen oder übermorgen vorlegen. Vor allen Dingen wollen wir daran festhalten, daß die schmerzlichen Ereignisse zum großen Teil aus dem Zurückweisen des Zusammenhanges mit der spirituellen Welt entstanden sind. Man mag daher die heutigen Zeitereignisse ein Karma des Materialismus nennen, aber man muß dann dieses Wort vom Karma des Materialismus nicht wiederum als Phrase nehmen, sondern man muß es in der richtigen Weise verstehen. Einsichten, die tief notwendig wären, sie sind in den Zeiten, die wir mehr oder weniger schon durchlebt haben, also in den letzten Jahrzehnten des 19. und den ersten Jahrzehnten des 20. Jahrhunderts, nur ganz sporadisch aufgetreten, nur da oder dort aufgetreten. Gewiß, es sind einige Einsichten - und auf Einsichten kommt vieles an -, es sind einige Einsichten in die Menschheit geworfen worden, und man hat auch versucht, diese so in die Menschheit zu werfen, daß schließlich eine größere Anzahl von Menschen hätte davon erfaßt werden können. Aber es gibt gegenwärtig - aus Gründen, die eben später erwähnt werden können - noch ein ungeheures Sträuben in der Menschheit gegen jedwede mögliche höhere, auf spiritueller Grundlage ruhende Einsicht.

So ist vor Jahren eine gewisse Schrift erschienen. Sie können sagen: Eine Schrift ist erschienen? Na, es erscheinen viele Schriften, was hat das denn für eine Bedeutung? Höchstens eine theoretische Bedeutung kann es haben, wenn eine Schrift erscheint - sie kann der Belehrung dienen —, denn davon, daß die Menschen dieses oder jenes lesen, kann das Heil der Welt nicht abhängen. - Dennoch hängt viel mehr, als man glaubt, davon ab, ob gewisse Ideen, gewisse Einsichten sich verbreiten - gerade wenn Sie noch einmal in Ihrer Seele überschauen, was ich in den letzten zwei, drei Vorträgen gesagt habe, so werden Sie das selber zugeben können. Ein Buch, sagte ich, ist erschienen, und der Verfasser dieses Buches ist Brooks Adams; es ist vor Jahren in Amerika erschienen. Damals schien mir dieses Buch als eine der bedeutsamsten Manifestationen neuerer Menscheneinsicht, wenn auch die Art, wie dieses Buch in die Welt geschickt worden ist, dadurch verdorben wurde, daß einer der allergrößten Phraseure der Gegenwart, nämlich der Expräsident Roosevelt, die Vorrede dazu geschrieben hat. Aber es bleibt doch bestehen, daß die Ideen dieses Buches von Brooks Adams im weitesten Sinne hätten aufklärend wirken können. Für das europäische Geistesleben kam auch noch in Betracht, daß zum Beispiel die deutsche Übersetzung dieses Buches von Brooks Adams in einem Verlage erschienen ist, von dem man wußte, daß er im Dienste ganz bestimmter geistiger Richtungen steht geistiger Richtungen, die der unsrigen, der anthroposophischen, ganz entschieden feindlich und abträglich sind. Aber darauf kommt es nicht an, sondern es handelt sich immer darum, ein Empfinden dafür zu haben, daß es von Bedeutung ist, wenn, ich möchte sagen gewisse Ideen unter solcher Flagge entsprechend in die Welt gesetzt werden. Denn es ist ein Unterschied, ob ein Buch, sagen wir im Cotta’sehen Verlage herausgegeben wird - einem angesehenen, vornehmen Verlage, der eben einfach Bücher erscheinen läßt -, oder ob ein Buch wie das angeführte in einem Verlage erscheint, in dem sonst Schriften im Dienste einer ganz besonderen Gesellschaft herausgegeben werden. Das ist ein großer Unterschied, ob man es nur mit Literatur oder ob man es mit gewollten Impulsen zu tun hat - das ist ein großer Unterschied!

Was enthält nun dieses Buch von Brooks Adams? Ich will Ihnen nur die Hauptideen entwickeln. Die Hauptideen werden in einer, ich möchte sogar sagen dilettantischen Weise - soweit man sie eben in ihrer Tragweite in Amerika erkennen konnte - ganz allgemein und abstrakt entwickelt. Aber zunächst ist es doch wichtig zu wissen, daß man von einer Stelle aus gewissermaßen versuchsweise solch einen «Vogel auffliegen» läßt. Die Ideen, die in diesem Buch entwickelt werden, sind etwa diese: Es gibt in der Welt verschiedene Völker, die durch lange Zeiten hindurch in Entwicklung begriffen sind. Man kann in der Entwicklung dieser Völker Aufgang und Niedergang verfolgen: sie werden geboren, sie machen ein Säuglingsalter, eine Jugendperiode durch, eine Periode des reifen Alters, ein Greisenleben, und sie gehen wieder zugrunde. Das ist natürlich zunächst keine tiefe Wahrheit, sondern nur ein Gerippe, aber was der Brooks Adams für diese Entwicklung der Völker als Gesetze entwickelt, das ist nun schon von einem gewissen Gewicht. So sagt er: Man kann beobachten, daß die Völker in der Regel in ihrer Jugend, wenn sie noch jugendliche Völker sind, mit Notwendigkeit zwei zusammengehörige Anlagen entwickeln. - Wenn man nun überhaupt eingehen will auf solche Ideen wie diese von Brooks Adams, so muß man natürlich Völker als solche von den einzelnen menschlichen Individuen, die zu den Völkern gehören, streng trennen und darf auch den Staatsbegriff nicht mit dem Volksbegriff verwechseln.

Gewisse Eigenschaften schreibt Brooks Adams also einer ganz bestimmten Entwicklungsperiode der Völker zu, und diese Eigenschaften gehören nach seiner Anschauung zusammen. So sagt er: Gewisse Völker haben in ihrem Jugendzeitalter erstens eine Anlage zur Imagination, das heißt, sie haben die Anlage, sich Vorstellungen zu bilden, welche vorzugsweise aus dem Inneren geschöpft sind, welche der produktiven Imagination ihren Ursprung verdanken - nicht der Überlegung, nicht dem, was man heute Wissenschaft nennt, sondern der schöpferischen Innenkraft des Menschen. - Solche Völker, meint Brooks Adams - ich referiere jetzt nur -, haben eine andere Eigenschaft, die notwendig damit verbunden ist, das heißt, diese Völker sind kriegerisch. Und untrennbar seien bei diesen Völkern von imaginativer Natur die Eigenschaften der Imagination und die kriegerischen Anlagen. Das hält er für ein Naturgesetz des geistigen Lebens dieser Völker. So ist für ihn zunächst gleichsam ein Typus von Völkern vorhanden: das sind die imaginativen und kriegerischen Völker.

Es gibt für ihn aber noch einen anderen Typus von Völkern. Das sind diejenigen Völker, bei denen nicht mehr die Imagination vorherrscht, sondern die Imagination ist zu dem geworden, was man kühles, wissenschaftliches Urteil nennt. Solche Völker, welche ein kühles, wissenschaftliches Urteil haben, sind durch ihre eigene Natur nicht kriegerisch, sondern industriell und kommerziell. Und diese beiden Eigenschaften - nicht von Menschen, sondern von Völkern -, diese beiden Eigenschaften, insofern sie als Volkseigenschaften auftreten, gehören zusammen: wissenschaftlich und kommerziell schließlich ist das Industrielle nur die Grundlage des Kommerziellen. Also auf der einen Seite wissenschaftlich-kommerziell, auf der andern Seite imaginativ-kriegerisch.

Ich will diese Ideen vorläufig nicht kritisieren, sondern ich will nur erwähnen, daß sich hier, wenn auch in dilettantischer Weise, ein Urteil geltend macht, welches vor Jahren aus Amerika gewissermaßen «aufflatterte» und das besagt: Hütet Euch zu glauben, Ihr könntet die Menschheit oder, sagen wir besser die menschlichen Stiefel über jeden beliebigen Leisten schlagen. Glaubt nicht, Ihr könnt beliebige Ideale aufstellen. Beachtet wohl, daß man nur von dem reden darf, was in der Evolution begründet ist, und daß man einem Volke, wie zum Beispiel dem slawischen, welches imaginativen Charakter hat, nicht zumuten soll, unkriegerisch zu sein. - Wer das Buch von Brooks Adams aufmerksam liest, der wird gerade auf das letzte Beispiel besonders hingewiesen.

Und man soll auch nicht nach dem äußeren Schein urteilen, sondern nach den inneren Werten, nach den inneren Affinitäten. Dilettantisch ist das Buch schon aus dem Grunde, meine lieben Freunde, weil eine solche Erkenntnis, wenn sie überhaupt ausgesprochen wird, nur ausgesprochen werden darf auf der Grundlage spiritueller Einsichten. Solange man aber nicht spirituelle Einsichten hat, werden Urteile über die Evolution der Menschheit, bei der spirituelle Mächte mitwirken, selbstverständlich immer einseitig sein, denn man wird vor allen Dingen eine große Wahrheit ausschließen - die große Wahrheit, daß man innerhalb der Maja steht, insofern man es auf dem physischen Plan mit den Ereignissen, aber auch mit dem Willen der Menschen zu tun hat. Nun, sobald man die Maja nicht als Maja behandelt, muß man, meine lieben Freunde, Irrtümern verfallen; man muß immer Irrtümern verfallen, wenn man die Maja als eine Wirklichkeit behandelt. Und als eine Wirklichkeit behandelt man die Maja aber meistens schon dadurch, daß man auf das Werden innerhalb der Maja und auf das, was dem Werden ähnlich ist, nicht die richtige Aufmerksamkeit wendet. Wieso?

Nun, nicht wahr, es wäre sehr schön, wenn es nicht ein Unsinn wäre, immer Frühling zu haben, immer blühende Pflanzen, immer sprossendes und sprießendes Leben zu haben. Und es könnte irgend jemand sagen: Warum haben es denn die Schöpfer der Welt nicht so eingerichtet, daß immer sprießendes, sprossendes Leben da ist? Warum müssen denn die schönen Tulpen, Lilien, Rosen abwelken und verfaulen? - Sehr einfach, nicht wahr: Damit sie wieder blühen können, deshalb müssen sie auch abwelken und verfaulen! - Insofern wir auf dem physischen Plan stehen, müssen wir uns klar sein, daß das eine ohne das andere nicht sein kann, ja, daß das eine um des andern willen da ist und daß der Goethe’sche Satz eine tiefe Wahrheit hat, die Natur habe den Tod erzeugt, um viel Leben zu haben. Weil die physische Welt die Maja ist, gibt es, solange man innerhalb der physischen Welt bleibt, keinen Ausgleich, sondern nur in dem Augenblicke gibt es einen Ausgleich, wenn man sich von der physischen zu der spirituellen Welt erheben kann. Dann wird dieser Ausgleich sich allerdings anders ausnehmen, als man glaubt, solange man die physische Welt für eine Wirklichkeit hält. Das heißt, es gibt eine Notwendigkeit, sich mit den Gesetzen der Maja bekannt zu machen und zu lernen, daß innerhalb der Maja nirgends ein Ausgleich gefunden werden kann, nicht durch Menschen und nicht durch andere Wesen, wenn nicht in die Maja dasjenige verwoben wird, was außerhalb der Maja liegt, was in der geistigen Wirklichkeit liegt.

Daher handelt es sich vor allen Dingen immer darum, die Maja als Maja kennenzulernen - kennenzulernen, wie sich die Dinge innerhalb der Maja verhalten, wo dem Aufblühen, dem Aufsprossen, dem Aufsprießen das Abwelken beigesellt sein muß. Der Natur gegenüber wird das jeder leicht zugeben können; er ist geneigt, weil man eben in der Natur mit der Nase darauf gestoßen wird, diese Tatsache anzuerkennen. So wird jeder leicht zur Einsicht zu bringen sein: Im Sommer oder im Herbst 1917 kann nur das zu Früchten reifen, was in der entsprechenden vorjährigen Aussaatperiode gesät worden ist. Hat man schlechte Samen gesät, können nur schlechte Früchte geerntet werden - ganz selbstverständlich. Und deshalb wird man geneigt sein, auf die Aussaat zu sehen, und wird sich in diesem Falle nicht so leicht von der Maja umgaukeln lassen wie auf einem andern Gebiete des menschlichen Lebens, wo die Dinge getrübt auftreten. Denn, sehen Sie, weist man zu irgendeiner Zeit in einer ähnlichen Weise auf so etwas hin, was im Völkerleben das Gleiche wie die schlechte Aussaat für das jährliche Reifen der Früchte bedeutet, ja, so stößt man sogleich auf Vorurteile. Und diese sind im Kaliber etwa dem gleich, was vorliegt, wenn ich einem Menschen sage: Na ja, du darfst dich nicht wundern, wenn du heute Schlechtes erntest, denn siehe einmal deine Aussaat an —, und er mir dann sofort sagt: Was? Das ist meine Aussaat, und wenn du über die Aussaat des vorigen Jahres irgend etwas sagst, dann triffst du mich. - Ich will ihn aber gar nicht treffen, denn er kann höchst unschuldig an der Aussaat sein. Es handelt sich gar nicht darum, jemanden persönlich zu treffen, sondern darum, objektiv den Tatbestand zu konstatieren. Es kann sich mir gar nicht darum handeln, irgendwie zu urteilen über den Zusammenhang zwischen ihm und seiner Aussaat — das mag seine Sache sein, das überlasse ich ihm ganz. Aber für die objektive Erkenntnis kann es sich darum handeln, die Aussaat wirklich zu prüfen und hinzusehen auf das, worum es sich tatsächlich handelt. Bleibt man dabei objektiv, so wird es vielleicht auch dem, der selbst an dieser Aussaat beteiligt war, von Nutzen sein, sofern ihn nicht ein anderer - ja, wie sagt man? - «übers Ohr gehauen» hat; er wird vielleicht sogar recht viel Nutzen daraus ziehen können, wenn man ihm den Zusammenhang zwischen Ernte und Aussaat klarmacht. Dieses möchte ich nur sagen, um Sie darauf hinzuweisen, daß es darauf ankommt, die Gedanken in die richtige Richtung zu lenken, in der richtigen Art zu suchen.

Und nun möchte ich, nachdem ich dies vorausgeschickt habe, etwas anführen - aus zwei verschiedenen Gründen, wie Sie gleich oder doch etwas später sehen werden. Ich habe im Verlaufe der hier in der letzten Zeit gehaltenen Betrachtungen aufmerksam gemacht auf einen König von England, der für England in bezug auf die religiöse Entwicklung auf dem Felde der Maja eine große Rolle spielte - gerade auf dem Felde der Maja eine große Rolle spielte: Heinrich VIII. Sie wissen, er hatte eine große Praxis im Sich-Entledigen seiner Frauen — er hatte es ja zu einer großen Anzahl von Frauen gebracht. Er hatte aber auch, na, sagen wir die Courage, sich vom Papste loszusagen, weil der Papst eine seiner Ehen nicht trennen wollte. Und aus diesem Grunde, weil der Papst eine seiner Ehen nicht trennen wollte, hatte dieser Heinrich VIII. die Courage, ganz England, soweit es von ihm abhing, eine neue Religion zu geben. Na ja, darüber haben wir also schon gesprochen.

Nun lebte während der Regierung Heinrichs VIII.—darauf habe ich auch schon aufmerksam gemacht - Thomas Morus, der große, bedeutende Thomas Morus. Er war ein Mann, der es in der damaligen Zeit Thomas Morus lebte in der Wende vom 15. ins 16. Jahrhundert -, in bezug auf die Geistigkeit zu jener Höhe brachte, auf der wir zum Beispiel auch den wunderbaren Pico della Mirandola finden und ähnliche bedeutende Persönlichkeiten. Dieser Thomas Morus war also ein erleuchteter Geist. Er hat es, trotzdem er ein erleuchteter Geist war, zum Staatskanzler Heinrichs VIII. gebracht, und er verachtete Heinrich VIII. nicht. Ich werde Ihnen gleich nachher den Beweis erbringen, daß er Heinrich VIII. nicht so ohne weiteres verachtet hat, weil er schon ein Geist war, der aus seinem Instinkte heraus — aus seinem erleuchteten Instinkte heraus — die Maja als Maja zu nehmen in der Lage war. Nun, Thomas Morus war aber zugleich ein frommer Mann wie Pico della Mirandola, ein aufrichtig frommer Mann, nicht solch ein frommer Mann wie Heinrich VII, auch nicht wie der Papst es war, aber ein aufrichtiger, ein ernsthaft frommer Mann. Und von seinem Gesichtspunkte aus lehnte er auch alle Reformationsversuche und alle reformatorischen Impulse, die ja in der damaligen Zeit schon aufgeleuchtet hatten, ab. Thomas Morus war in einer gewissen Beziehung ein treuer Sohn der katholischen Kirche, und er war nicht geneigt, mit dem König mitzugehen, wenn er auch aller Ehren teilhaftig geworden wäre, er war nicht geneigt mitzugehen, trotzdem er sogar Staatskanzler geworden war. Er war dennoch nicht geneigt, sich einfach deshalb einer anderen Religion anzuschließen, weil Heinrich VIII. eine andere Frau wollte. Deshalb wurde er nicht nur abgesetzt, sondern auch zum Tode verurteilt. Und die Akten dieses Prozesses, in dem er zum Tode verurteilt wurde — sie sind außerordentlich interessant und, meine lieben Freunde, sehr bezeichnend für die damalige Zeit. Wenn man das Gerichtsurteil liest, mit dem Thomas Morus zum Tode verurteilt worden ist, so hat es einen merkwürdigen Wortlaut - einen wirklich merkwürdigen Wortlaut; dieser Wortlaut stimmt bis zu dem Grade, in dem man so etwas vollzieht, überein mit etwas anderem.

Die meisten von Ihnen werden es wissen, denn das steht längst alles in profanen Büchern, daß in den gebräuchlichen Freimaurerorden das Aufsteigen durch die Grade mit gewissen Formeln verbunden ist und daß in diesen Formeln auch die Angabe der Todesart enthalten ist, die denjenigen treffen soll, der das entsprechende Geheimnis dieses Grades nicht wahrt. Da wird ihm gesagt, daß er unter diesen oder jenen Umständen eines furchtbaren Todes zu sterben habe, in einem bestimmten Grade zum Beispiel, daß ihm der Leib aufzuschneiden sei und seine Asche in alle Winde, nach allen vier Weltgegenden, zerstreut werden solle. Wie gesagt, diese Dinge sind ja heute schon Gegenstand zahlreicher profaner Schriften geworden. Das über Thomas Morus gefällte Urteil stimmt nun durchaus mit einer bestimmten Gradformel überein: Er sollte auf unmenschliche Weise vom Leben zum Tode befördert werden. Aber damit wollte man sich nicht begnügen, man wollte auch seinen Leichnam in so viele Stücke zerteilen, als es Weltgegenden gibt, und die Teile in die verschiedenen Weltgegenden zerstreuen. Zu einem gewissen Teil ist das Urteil auch so vollstreckt worden.

Nun bedenken Sie, daß wir mit diesem Ereignis immerhin - Thomas Moraus ist in der zweiten Hälfte des 15. Jahrhunderts geboren, in der ersten Hälfte des 16. Jahrhunderts stirbt er -, im Beginne der fünften nachatlantischen Periode stehen. Die Frage aber, meine lieben Freunde, darf gestattet sein: Hat Thomas Morus sonst nichts getan, als daß er einfach den Suprematseid nicht geschworen hat, das heißt wollte er bloß nicht anerkennen, daß nun die englische Kirche vom Papst unabhängig zu sein habe und anzunehmen habe, was Heinrich VIII. verhängt? Hatte er nicht auch anderes getan? Nun wollen wir seine bedeutendste Tat ins Auge fassen - eine Tat, die auch heute noch die allergrößte Bedeutung haben kann für den, der sie ordentlich ins Auge faßt. Thomas Morus hat das Buch «Utopia» geschrieben «Über die beste Art des Staates und die neue Insel Utopia». Dieses Buch handelt in seinem Hauptteil von den Einrichtungen der Insel Utopia, also über das Land «an keinem Ort», man könnte sagen über das «Nirgend-Land». Aber wer das Buch von Thomas Morus im richtigen Sinne liest, der wird sehen, daß es dem Thomas Morus auf die «Utopia» viel mehr ankommt als auf irgendein Land der äußeren physischen Wirklichkeit. Freilich, wenn man in dem Sinne töricht ist, daß man bei einem Mann wie Thomas Morus voraussetzt, er habe seine «Utopia» einfach geschrieben, um irgend etwas aus der Phantasie heraus zu dichten - mit anderen Worten, wenn man so über die Utopisten redet wie diejenigen, die sich besonders gescheit dünken, dann darf Thomas Morus nicht zu den Utopisten gerechnet werden, denn er wollte natürlich nicht bloß irgendein Phantasiegebilde vor die Menschen hinstellen, sondern er hat - so wie das in seiner Zeit möglich war — viel mehr mit einer solchen Sache sagen wollen. Der Hauptteil des Buches handelt von «Utopia», aber das Buch hat eine Einleitung, und diese Einleitung enthält ganz Mannigfaltiges; sie enthält auch, ich möchte sagen die Aufschlüsse darüber, warum Thomas Morus das Buch über die Insel Utopia geschrieben hat. Er erzählt darin ungefähr folgendes. Er sagt - und das ist eine wichtige Stelle, auf die ich Sie doch aufmerksam machen möchte, damit Sie sehen, daß er Heinrich VII. nicht verachtet hat -, er beginnt ja gleich so:

Heinrich VIII, der unüberwindliche König von England, ein Fürst von seltenem und überlegenem Geiste, hatte vor nicht langer Zeit einen Zwist von gewisser Bedeutung mit dem durchlauchtigen Karl Prinzen von Kastilien. Ich wurde damals mit der Mission, diese Angelegenheiten zu ordnen und möglichst ins Reine zu bringen, als Gesandter nach Flandern geschickt.

Nun ja, bei dieser Gelegenheit, da er als Gesandter in Angelegenheiten Heinrichs VIIL, den er einen erleuchteten und großen König nennt, nach Flandern geschickt wird, lernt er einen Mann kennen, den er — wie er erzählt - außerordentlich gescheit findet, geistig außerordentlich bedeutend findet, so daß er, [das heißt eigentlich sein Freund], den Mann fragt: Ja, wenn Sie so viele ausgezeichnete Dinge wissen und richtig beurteilen können, wie es der Fall ist bei Ihnen, warum stellen Sie Ihre Einsichten nicht in den Dienst dieses oder jenes Fürsten? - Thomas Morus meint nämlich, daß diejenigen, die im Dienste eines Fürsten stehen, zumeist nicht sehr erleuchtete Menschen sind und daß außerordentlich viel Gutes und Günstiges in der Welt geschehen könnte, wenn sich so erleuchtete Menschen in den Dienst von Fürsten stellen würden. Da erwidert der betreffende Mann: Das würde alles nichts nützen, denn würde ich in irgendeinem Ministerium meine Ansichten vorbringen, dann würde ich nicht die andern gescheiter machen, sondern sie würden mich - es ist nicht mit diesen Worten erzählt, aber es steht wirklich so darinnen - sehr bald hinauswerfen; ich würde gar nichts nützen, wenn ich das täte. Und um gewissermaßen zu erhärten, daß dieser Mann tatsächlich gelebt hat, dem er von sich aus angeblich nicht Recht gibt, erzählt Thomas Morus noch das Folgende. Er sagt: Ich kam dann mit diesem Manne in einer Gesellschaft zusammen, da waren die verschiedensten Leute, und da erzählte denn dieser Mann auch, wie er einmal in einer andern Gesellschaft versucht habe, seine Ansichten zu entwickeln.

Es handelt sich hier nicht bloß um eine Einleitung zu «Utopia», sondern Thomas Morus will vielmehr - und das ist das Kuriose — auf diese Weise eine Kritik des damaligen Englands geben, also des Englands von der Wende des 15. Jahrhunderts ins 16. Jahrhundert. Der englische Staatskanzler will also eine Kritik Englands geben. Wer nun so denkt wie Thomas Morus, gibt nicht eine Kritik eines Abstraktums, wenn er von England spricht, denn er weiß, daß das englische Volk etwas anderes ist als diejenigen, die in Betracht kommen, wenn man von der Konfiguration des englischen Staatswesens spricht - er weiß das ganz gut. Und er weiß, daß dieses Staatswesen auch nicht ein bloßes Abstraktum ist, sondern daß es gemacht wird von einzelnen; er weiß, daß man wirklich nicht das englische Volk kritisiert, wenn man die Handlungen dieser einzelnen kritisiert, von deren Konfigurationen aber alles abhängt, worauf es ankommt, wenn man vom englischen Staatswesen spricht. Thomas Morus nimmt also den besten, den bestmöglichen Ansatz, um konkret zu werden, denn es ist natürlich kein konkreter, sondern bloß ein unsinniger Ansatz, wenn man sagt: England ist so, Deutschland ist so, Italien ist so und so weiter -, denn damit redet man eigentlich in Wirklichkeit von nichts.

Nun läßt er diesen Mann, der wie gesagt ein gescheiter, erleuchteter Mensch war, in einer größeren Gesellschaft zusammenkommen mit einem andern Mann, der ein «ausgezeichneter» Jurist war - also das war, was so die Welt einen ausgezeichneten Juristen nennt -, und er läßt diese beiden, also den gescheiten Menschen und den nach dem Urteil der Welt ausgezeichneten Menschen, in eine Diskussion über die englische Jurisprudenz kommen. Nun, die englische Jurisprudenz war damals noch nicht so, wie die heutige ist, aber das tut ja nichts — wir stehen eben doch im Beginne des fünften nachatlantischen Zeitraums. Der gescheite Mensch fand, daß man außerordentlich töricht handle, wenn man gegen Diebe so vorgehe, wie man im damaligen England gegen Diebe vorging. Er fand, daß das gar nicht besonders gescheit sei. Überhaupt, die ganze Art und Weise, über den Diebstahl ‚oder über ähnliches zu denken, fand er gar nicht besonders gescheit; der Mann, der Utopia gesehen hat und es später auch beschreibt, fand das gar nicht gescheit, was dazumal an Ansichten vorhanden war, wie man sich zum Beispiel einem Dieb gegenüber zu benehmen habe, denn er fand, daß man vor allen Dingen nachzuforschen habe, woher seine Motive kämen. Dem «ausgezeichneten» Juristen war das selbstverständlich eine vollständig unverständliche Sache. Aber nun wollen wir uns wirklich mit den Auseinandersetzungen dieses gescheiten Menschen - nicht des «ausgezeichneten» Menschen - ein klein wenig bekannt machen. Dieser gescheite Mensch sagt:

Eines Tages war ich bei diesem Prälaten zu Tisch. Der Zufall ließ mich dort auf einen Laien treffen, der jedoch in dem Rufe eines großen Rechtskundigen stand. Dieser Mensch überhäufte, ich weiß nicht zu welchem Zweck, die strenge Justiz gegen die Diebe mit Lobpreisungen. Mit groRem Wohlbehagen erzählte er, wie man sie hier und dort zu Zwanzigen an einem und dem nämlichen Galgen aufknüpfte. «Und dennoch», fügte er hinzu, «welcher Übelstand! Von all diesen Spitzbuben entgehen kaum zwei oder drei dem Strick, und England liefert deren von allen Seiten neue.» Mit jener Ungezwungenheit der Rede, die ich dem Kardinal gegenüber beobachtete, sagte ich darauf: «Darin liegt nichts, worüber Sie sich wundern dürften.»

Also jetzt redet der gescheite Mensch.

«In dieser Beziehung ist der Tod eine ebenso ungerechte als unnütze Strafe. Um den Diebstahl zu bestrafen, ist sie zu grausam, und um ihn zu verhindern, zu schwach. Der einfache Diebstahl verdient den Galgen nicht, und die schrecklichste Buße wird denjenigen nicht vom Stehlen zurückschrecken, dem nur dies eine Mittel übrigbleibt, um nicht Hungers zu sterben. Hierin gleicht die Justiz Englands und mancher anderen Länder einem schlechten Lehrer, der seine Schüler lieber schlägt als unterrichtet. Man unterzieht die Diebe den schrecklichsten Martern. Wäre es nicht besser, allen Gliedern der Gesellschaft die Existenz zu sichern, damit niemand sich in die Notwendigkeit versetzt sähe, zuerst zu stehlen und dann vom Leben zum Tode gebracht zu werden?»

«Dafür ist von der Gesellschaft gesorgt», erwiderte mein Rechtskundiger, «die Industrie, der Ackerbau bieten dem Volke eine Menge von Existenzmitteln, aber es gibt Geschöpfe, die das Verbrechen der Arbeit vorziehen.» «Jetzt sind Sie, wo ich Sie haben wollte!», erwiderte ich.

Der Gescheite spricht jetzt wieder:

«Von denjenigen, die mit Wunden bedeckt aus inneren oder auswärtigen Kriegen heimkehren, will ich gar nicht einmal reden, obgleich ich dazu wohl Grund hätte. Denn wie viele Soldaten verloren nicht in der Schlacht von Cornwallis oder in dem Feldzuge gegen Frankreich ein oder mehrere Glieder im Dienste des Königs und des Vaterlandes! Diese Unglücklichen waren zu schwach geworden, um ihr altes Handwerk fortzutreiben, und zu alt, um noch ein neues zu erlernen. Aber lassen wir das; wir leben nicht immer in Kriegszeiten. Werfen wir die Augen auf das, was täglich um uns her vorfällt.

Die vornehmste Ursache des öffentlichen Elends besteht in der überäßigen Anzahl von Edeln, die sich, gleich müßigen Hornissen, von ihres Nächsten Schweiß und Arbeit nähren und die ihre Ländereien bebauen

lassen, indem sie, um ihre Revenuen zu vermehren, ihre Pächter bis aufs Blut aussaugen; eine andere Ökonomie kennen sie nicht. Aber handelt es sich darum, sich ein Vergnügen zu verschaffen, so sind sie verschwenderisch bis zum Wahnsinn, und sollten sie dadurch an den Bettelstab geraten. Nicht minder beklagenswert ist cs, daß sie ganze Scharen von müßigen Dienern, die nichts gelernt, wodurch sie sich ihre Existenz sichern könnten, in ihrem Gefolge haben.

Wenn diese Diener erkranken oder ihren Herrn durch den Tod verlieren, gibt man ihnen den Abschied, denn man will lieber Müßiggänger als Kranke ernähren, und häufig ist auch der Erbe des Verstorbenen nicht fähig, die ihm überkommene Dienerschaft fortzuhalten.

Nun sind diese Leute, wenn sie nicht das Herz haben zu stehlen, dem Hungertode ausgesetzt. In der Tat, was bleibt ihnen übrig? Während sie ein neues Unterkommen suchen, reiben sie ihre Gesundheit und ihre Kleider auf; und wenn die Krankheit sie gebleicht und die Zeit sie in Lumpen gehüllt hat, erschrickt man vor dem Gedanken, sie in Dienst zu nehmen. Selbst die Bauern fühlen sich dazu nicht gedrungen. Von einem Menschen, der sich von Jugend auf im Müßiggange und in Vergnügungen bewegt hat, der nur Säbel und Schild zu tragen, mit stolzem Auge auf die Nachbarschaft herabzusehen und alle Welt zu verachten gewohnt ist - von einem solchen Menschen wissen sie recht gut, daß er sich wenig dazu eignet, den Spaten und den Karst zu handhaben und im Dienste eines armen Landmanns um geringen Lohn und karge Nahrung getreulich zu arbeiten.»

«Gerade diese Menschenklasse ist es», ließ sich mein Gegner hierauf vernehmen, «die der Staat mit der größten Sorgfalt unterhalten und vervielfältigen muß. Bei ihnen findet man mehr Mut und geistige Tüchtigkeit als beim Handwerker und Ackersmann. Sie sind größer und stärker, und gehen sie zum Heere ab, so darf man, wenn eine Schlacht geliefert werden soll, gerade von ihnen am meisten erwarten.»

«Mit anderen Worten», erwiderte ich, [...]

- also jetzt kommt wieder der gescheite Mann —

[...] «um den Waffen Ruhm und Erfolg zu sichern, muß man die Diebe vervielfältigen. Denn für die letzteren bilden jene Müßiggänger eine unerschöpfliche Schule, und beim Licht betrachtet, sind Spitzbuben nicht die schlechtesten Soldaten, und Soldaten sind nicht die furchtsamsten Spitzbuben; es gibt viel Analoges zwischen diesen beiden Metiers. Unglücklicherweise leidet nicht England allein an dieser gesellschaftlichen Wunde; sie haftet fast an allen Nationen.

Eine noch weit gefährlichere Pest nagt an dem inneren Leben Frankreichs. Jeder Fußbreit Landes ist dort mit Truppen wie besät, die vom Staat in Regimenter verteilt und besoldet werden. Und dies geschieht in Friedenszeiten - wenn man anders Pausen, in welchen der Krieg kaum mehr als Atem schöpft, so nennen darf. Dies traurige System rechtfertigt man mit dem nämlichen Grunde, nach welchem es Ihnen notwendig scheint, Myriaden untätiger Diener zu unterhalten. Gewisse furchtsame und finstere Politiker sind der Ansicht gewesen, als erfordere die Sicherheit des Staats eine zahlreiche, starke, beständig unter den Waffen stehende und aus Veteranen zusammengesetzte Armee. Neulingen wagen sie sich nicht anzuvertrauen. Man sollte fast meinen, daß sie den Krieg nur deshalb erregten, um dem Soldaten das Exerzitium beizubringen und, wie Sallust sagt, um durch diese große Menschenschlächterei zu verhindern, daß sein Herz und seine Hand einschlafen.

Frankreich lernt auf seine Unkosten die Gefahr kennen, diese Art fleischfressender Tiere zu ernähren. Gleichwohl dürfte es seine Augen nur auf die Römer, die Karthaginenser und eine Menge anderer Völker des Altertums werfen. Was ist ihnen aus diesen ungeheueren und immer schlagfertigen Armeen erwachsen? Die Verwüstung ihrer Länder, die Zerstörung ihrer Städte, der Untergang ihres Reichs. Ja, wenn es den Franzosen noch genützt hätte, ihre Soldaten gleichsam schon als Säuglinge einzuexerzieren! Aber Frankreichs Veteranen haben mit den Neugeworbenen Englands zu tun gehabt, und ich weiß nicht, ob sie sich rühmen können, häufig die Oberhand behalten zu haben. Ich will über dieses Kapitel schweigen; es möchte den Anschein haben, als suchte ich denjenigen, die mir zuhören, zu schmeicheln.»

So der Staatskanzler Thomas Morus. Man sieht, daß man eigentlich heute von diesem Staatskanzler nur das abzuschreiben braucht, was er dazumal mit Bezug auf die Armeen Frankreichs gesagt hat, und Sie könnten damit die allerschönsten Sätze fabrizieren und sie den englischen Ministern vorlegen, um gegen den «preußischen Militarismus» zu wettern. Nur sind wir am Beginne des fünften nachatlantischen Zeitraums, und vielleicht könnte die Zusammenstellung der heutigen Redereien mit dem, was dazumal am Ausgangspunkt der Dinge lag, unangenehm berühren nach gewissen Richtungen hin!

Nun, sehen Sie, Thomas Morus läßt einen Menschen reden - meinetwillen können Sie sagen, daß er ihn fingiert -, er läßt einen Menschen reden, der versucht, den Dingen auf den Grund zu kommen, und zwar in einer Weise versucht, den Dingen auf den Grund zu kommen, die manchen Leuten unangenehm ist, selbst wenn die Dinge überhaupt nur angetippt werden. Aber er geht nun weiter und sagt:

«Von welcher Seite ich die Frage betrachten mag, diese unzählige Masse von müßigen Menschen scheint mir für das Land, selbst für den Fall eines Krieges, der sich übrigens immer vermeiden läßt, ohne Nutzen. Dem Frieden gereicht sie außerdem zu einer wahren Plage; und der Friede verdient wohl, daß man sich mit ihm ebenso angelegentlich beschäftigt als mit dem Kriege.

Aber der Herren- und Bedientenstand sind nicht die einzigen Ursachen der Diebereien, von welchen Sie heimgesucht werden. Es gibt eine andere, die ausschließlich Ihrer Insel eigentümlich ist.»

So sagt der Mann, der aus Utopia kommt und der seinen Zuhörern etwas beibringen möchte über die Eigentümlichkeiten dieses Staates.

«Und worin besteht diese?», fragte der Kardinal.

Also auch einer, der sich an der Unterhaltung beteiligt.

«In den unzähligen Schafherden; die heutigen Tages ganz: England bedecken, Diese überall anderswo so sanften und genügsamen Tiere sind bei Ihnen so gefräßig und grausam, daß sie sich selbst an den Menschen vergreifen und sie von den Feldern, aus den Häusern und Dörfern verjagen.

In der Tat, nach allen Punkten des Königreichs, wo man die feinste und kostbarste Wolle einsammelt, sieht man die Vornehmen, die Reichen und sogar sehr ehrwürdige Abbés hinzueilen, um sich das Terrain streitig zu machen. Ihre Renten, ihre Privilegien, die Revenuen ihrer Ländereien genügen diesen armen Leuten nicht; sie sind nicht zufrieden damit, in Untätigkeit und Vergnügungen zu leben, der Öffentlichkeit zur Last und dem Staat ohne Nutzen. In Umkreisen von vielen Meilen entfremden sie den Boden der Kultur, sie verwandeln ihn in Weiden, sie reißen Häuser und Dörfer nieder und verschonen nur die Kirchen - um Stallungen für ihre Hammel zu erhalten. Die bewohntesten und am besten kultivierten Stellen schaffen sie in Einöden um. Ohne Zweifel fürchten sie, daß es zu viele Gärten und Holzungen geben und daß es den wilden Tieren an Boden fehlen möchte.

So umzieht ein habsüchtiger Nimmersatt mehrere tausend Morgen Landes mit einer einzigen Ringmauer; rechtschaffene Landleute werden aus ihren Häuser verjagt, die einen durch Betrug; die anderndurehiGewält, die Glücklichsten durch eine Kettenreihe von Bedrückungen und Plakkereien, wodurch sie gezwungen werden, ihre Besitztümer zu verkaufen. Und dann wandern diese Familien, die weniger reich als zahlreich sind denn der Ackerbau verlangt viele Hände - über die Felder davon, Männer und Frauen, Witwen und Waisen, Väter und Mütter mit kleinen Kindern. Weinend fliehen die Unglücklichen das Dach, unter welchem sie geboren wurden, den Boden, der sie ernährte, und wissen nicht, wo sie eine Zufluchtsstätte suchen sollen. Um einen niedrigen Preis veräußern sie dann dasjenige, was sie von ihren Effekten haben mitnehmen können Gegenstände, die schon an und für sich nur einen geringen Wert haben. Ist diese schwache Quelle erschöpft, was bleibt ihnen übrig? Der Diebstahl und später ein regelrechtes Gehängtwerden.

Vielleicht ziehen sie es vor, ihr Elend als Bettler fortzuschleppen. Aber dann zögert man nicht, sie als Vagabunden und Menschen ohne Heimat ins Gefängnis zu werfen. Und worin besteht gleichwohl ihr Verbrechen? Es besteht in nichts anderem, als daß sie niemand finden können, der ihnen Arbeit gäbe, obgleich sie nur diese auf das Eifrigste suchen. Wer wird sie auch beschäftigen können? Sie verstehen nur das Feld zu bebauen; es gibt also da, wo weder an Saat noch Ernte mehr zu denken ist, für sie nichts zu tun. Ein einziger Schaf- oder Kuhhirt genügt jetzt, um Ländereien abweiden zu lassen, deren Bestellung früher mehrere Hundert Arme erheischte.

Eine andere Folge dieses verderblichen Systems ist der in mehreren Gegenden sehr hohe Preis der Lebensmittel.

Aber das ist nicht alles. Seit der Vervielfältigung der Weideplätze hat eine pestartige Vichseuche eine unermeßliche Anzahl von Schafen getötet. Es scheint fast, als hätte der Himmel die unersättliche Habsucht ihrer Zusammenraffer durch diese schreckliche Sterblichkeit bestrafen wollen, die er gerechter gegen ihre eigenen Köpfe gekehrt hätte. Der Preis der Wolle ist demgemäß so hoch gestiegen, daß die unbemittelten Tucharbeiter gegenwärtig keine mehr kaufen können. Und da haben Sie abermals eine Masse von arbeitslosen Leuten. Es ist nicht zu leugnen, daß die Zahl der Schafe täglich in außerordentlichen Verhältnissen wächst; der Preis derselben ist aber nichtsdestoweniger deshalb um Nichts gesunken, weil der Wollhandel, wenngleich er kein gesetzliches Monopol ist, sich in der Tat ausschließlich in den Händen einiger reichen Sammler befindet, die nichts zum Verkaufe drängt und die daher nur mit den größten Vorteilen verkaufen.»

Nun, ich will diese Stelle nicht weiter vorlesen, meine lieben Freunde; ich will nur bemerken, daß Sie hier den Staatskanzler Thomas Morus, den Gesinnungsgenossen des Pico della Mirandola, eine herbe Kritik ausüben sehen durch den - meinetwillen fingierten - Menschen, der aus Utopia kommt, aber eine Kritik an etwas, was dazumal da war, was wirklich geschehen ist, denn dieses ist wirklich geschehen: daß über weite Gebiete hin die Leute von ihren Ländereien vertrieben worden sind, daß man jene, die mit ihren Händen den Boden bebauten, ausgetrieben hat und ihre Ländereien zu Stätten für die Schafherden der Grundbesitzer gemacht hat, die auf diese Weise eben durchaus den Ertrag der Wolle haben wollten. Daß es notwendig ist, an dieser Stelle einzugreifen, daß es solche Menschen gibt, welche die Leute von Land und Boden vertreiben, um diesen für Schafherden zu verwenden - das fand Thomas Morus notwendig zu sagen.

Und jene Menschen, meine lieben Freunde, die in objektiver Weise die Wirkungen mit ihren Ursachen verknüpfen, können jetzt auf dem physischen Plan verfolgen, wie die heutige Gestalt des englischen Staates innig zusammenhängt mit dem, was dazumal geschehen ist und was von Thomas Morus in dieser Weise kritisiert wird. Und wenn man dem nachgeht mit den Mitteln, die es schon auch gibt, meine lieben Freunde, dann wird man finden: Das englische Volk ist für vieles nicht verantwortlich, wofür das politische England sehr wohl verantwortlich ist. Aber diejenigen, die für das politische England verantwortlich sind, die sind die Nachfolger und bis zu einem gewissen Grade sogar die Blutsnachfolger derer, die hier von Thomas Morus kritisiert werden. Da ist eine kontinuierliche Entwicklung, die bis dahin zurückreicht. Und wenn man solche Dinge ins Auge faßt, dann wird man wissen und finden können, daß in solchen Reden wie derjenigen von Lord Rosebery, die ich Ihnen neulich angeführt habe, mit drinnenstecken die Stimmen derer, welche sich dazumal auf diese Weise das Erträgnis aus der Wolle verschafften. Man muß überall nach den objektiven Zusammenhängen suchen.

Vor allen Dingen aber muß man den Anspruch machen, nicht in einer beliebigen Weise mißverstanden zu werden. Was heißt es denn, wenn jemand einem vorwirft: Du solltest zartfühlender sein, denn der Engländer muß so und so denken! - Darum handelt es sich gar nicht, sondern es handelt sich darum, daß gewisse Dinge in unserem jetzigen Leben zurückgehen auf gewisse Ursachen und daß man diese Ursachen an den rechten Stellen suchen muß. Die wirklich echten Nachkommen, ja die Blutsnachkommen derjenigen, die dazumal die Leute von Haus und Hof, von Grund und Boden vertrieben haben, um Schafherden zu halten statt die Äcker zu belassen - diese Leute und ihre Impulse zu verteidigen, hat gewiß niemand aus dem Grunde eine Veranlassung, weil er Engländer ist. Es handelt sich also darum, meine lieben Freunde, sich ein wenig bekannt zu machen mit den Gesetzen, mit denen man es eigentlich zu tun hat, und auf das hinzuschauen, was real in der Welt ist, und nicht zu schwätzen, diese Nation habe dieses oder jenes verschuldet.

Ich werde jetzt, nachdem ich versucht habe, Ihnen einen charakteristischen Zusammenhang zwischen etwas, was in der Gegenwart ist, und etwas, was in der Vergangenheit war, vor Augen zu führen, ich werde jetzt an einen ganz andern Punkt gehen, um dann die einzelnen Punkte zusammenzuführen. Ich werde Ihnen einige Tatsachen vorlegen, weil es sich wirklich darum handelt, meine lieben Freunde, daß Sie Unterlagen bekommen sollen für Ihre Urteile; ich werde Ihnen jetzt einige mehr äußere Tatsachen vorlegen.

Wenn wir das gegenwärtige Europa überschauen, mit Ausnahme des von Slawen bewohnten östlichen Teiles, so finden wir, daß ein großer Teil dieses Europas hervorgegangen ist aus dem, was man für das 8. und 9. Jahrhundert das Reich Karls des Großen nennt. Dieses Reich Karls des Großen - wir wollen es nicht weiter charakterisieren, wir wollen auch nicht darauf Rücksicht nehmen, daß sich heute die verschiedensten Menschen um Karl den Großen streiten, denn dieses Streiten um Karl den Großen hat wirklich fast so viel Sinn, als wenn sich drei Söhne um ihren Vater streiten und dabei alle drei das Recht haben, den einen ihren Vater zu nennen. Es ist doch sehr häufig der Fall, daß sich drei Menschen nicht um etwas streiten würden, wenn sie nicht einen gemeinsamen Vater hätten, denn dann fiele das Streitobjekt wahrscheinlich weg - nämlich die Erbschaft!

Aus dem Reiche Karls des Großen sind im wesentlichen drei Teilgebiete hervorgegangen: der westliche Teil, der nach verschiedenen Wechselfällen zum heutigen Frankreich wurde, ein östlicher Teil, der im wesentlichen zum heutigen Deutschland und Österreich führte, mit Ausnahme der slawischen und magyarischen Gebiete, und ein mittlerer Teil, der im wesentlichen zu dem heutigen Italien wurde. Im Grunde genommen haben alle drei Teile absolut das gleiche Recht, sich auf Karl den Großen zurückzuführen. Und manchmal kann es ja sogar von merkwürdigen Empfindungen abhängen, ob die Menschen sich auf Karl den Großen zurückführen lassen wollen oder nicht - wenn jemandem einfällt, wie viele Sachsen Karl der Große hat abschlachten lassen, so könnte es sein, daß er gar kein besonderes Gewicht darauf legt, sich auf Karl den Großen zurückgeführt zu finden! Nun, diese drei Gebiete gingen also aus dem Reiche Karls des Großen hervor. Wenn wir vieles von dem verstehen wollen, was heute geschieht, so müssen wir auch ins Auge fassen, daß zwischen dem eigentlichen mittleren Gebiete und dem östlichen Gebiete durch das ganze Mittelalter hindurch gewisse Beziehungen bestanden, welche idealer Natur waren - solche Beziehungen, wie man sie heute auf diesem Felde, wenn man nicht gewisse Phrasen für ernst nehmen will, überhaupt nicht mehr kennt, denn was schließlich dem Heiligen Römischen Reich zugrunde lag, das waren schon zum großen Teil ideale Gründe. Und wer es nicht glauben will, daß es ideale Gründe waren, der lese einmal die Schrift über die Monarchie von Dante oder unterrichte sich sonst über die Art und Weise, wie Dante über diese Dinge dachte. Und er nehme nur einmal Rücksicht, daß Dante es war, der zum Beispiel dem Rudolf von Habsburg vorwarf, daß er sich zu wenig um Italien kümmere, den «schönsten Garten des Reiches». Dante war - wenigstens in dem Teil seines Lebens, auf den es vor allem ankommt -, ein absoluter Anhänger jener Idealgemeinschaft, welche sich da begründet hatte und die Deutschland-Italien hieß.

Nun sehen wir die Republik Venedig vom 13., 14. Jahrhundert an sich gewissermaßen auflehnen gegen das, was vom Norden kam. Zwar verschlang Venedig das Patriarchat Aquileia, vor allen Dingen aber war es der Republik Venedig darauf angekommen, festen Fuß an der Adria, in den Küstengegenden der Adria, zu fassen. Nun, die Republik Venedig hatte viel Erfolg dazumal, und wir sehen, wie in der Tat dasjenige, was vom Norden kam, gerade unter dem Einflusse der Republik Venedig zurückgedrängt wurde. Dann kommt - ich habe es bei einer anderen Gelegenheit hier erörtert - das, was als die Renaissance bekannt ist, die gewissermaßen unter dem Eindrucke des Aufblühens der freien Städte auch in Italien groß wird. Dann kommt aber die Gegenreformation, die Politik, die von päpstlich-spanischer Seite ausgeht. Und wir sehen, daß man im Grunde genommen erst wiederum vom 18. Jahrhundert ab in Italien daran denken kann, sich zu erholen von jahrhundertelangen Schmerzen und Leiden. Und ich brauche nun nicht auszuführen - es kann das in jedem Geschichtswerk nachgelesen werden -, wie dann der Zeitpunkt heranrückte, in dem Italien unter dem Beifall der ganzen Welt seine Einigkeit fand. Und wer die Verhältnisse kennt, der weiß, daß nirgends mehr als in deutschen Gebieten - nun, vielleicht nirgends mehr kann man nicht sagen, aber jedenfalls ebensoviel als irgendwo sonst an Begeisterung für die Einigkeit Italiens aufgebracht worden ist.

Aber nun kann die Frage aufgeworfen werden: Wie ist denn die moderne Einheit Italiens zustande gekommen? Und diese Vereinigung Italiens, meine lieben Freunde, müssen wir als Beispiel ins Auge fassen - als ein besonders wichtiges Beispiel, wie die Einheit von Staaten zustande kommt. Und auf der andern Seite müssen wir den Zusammenhang verstehen lernen zwischen dem, was ich Ihnen vor acht Tagen oder letzten Sonntag über die Vorgänge in Serbien erzählt habe, und den Vorgängen in Italien, denn da gibt es Zusammenhänge, die für ein Verständnis der Verhältnisse von ungeheurer Wichtigkeit sind. Aber man muß zuerst ein wenig ins Auge fassen, wie das Staatsgefüge Italiens, das gewiß neidlos anzuerkennende Staatsgefüge Italiens, zustande gekommen ist.

Nicht wahr, man braucht da ja nur zurückzugehen bis zur Schlacht von Solferino, wo Frankreich auf der Seite von Italien stand und wo der erste Schritt gemacht wurde zu der späteren Gestaltung des modernen italienischen Staates. Da stehen wir also in den fünfziger Jahren des 19. Jahrhunderts. Und wir dürfen uns fragen: Wodurch ist es denn dazumal möglich geworden - denn die Sache stand ja wirklich recht sehr auf dem Spiele -, wodurch ist es denn dazumal möglich geworden? Lesen Sie die Geschichte, Sie werden das voll bewahrheitet finden, was ich Ihnen jetzt sage. Wodurch ist es denn möglich geworden, daß eben der erste Schritt auf dem Pfade des modernen Italiens durch Italien und Frankreich getan werden konnte bei Solferino? Dadurch, daß sich dazumal Preußen und Österreich Österreich hatte ja nur zu verlieren - nicht vereinigen konnten! Was dann später geschehen ist, ist dem zu verdanken, daß Italien in Camillo Cavour einen wirklich großen Staatsmann hatte, in dessen Seele die Idee aufging, in Italien, von diesem Anfang ausgehend, etwas zu bewirken, was wie zu einer Art Wiederaufleben alter römischer Größe führen könnte. Aber die Sache nahm einen andern Verlauf, und ich möchte sagen, etwas Ähnliches, wenn auch vielleicht mit einer ganz anderen Note, etwas Ähnliches, wie wir es gesehen haben bei dem Übergange von dem edlen Serbenfürsten Michael Obrenovič zu den späteren serbischen Herrschern, finden wir bei dem Übergang von der großen Seele Camillo Cavours zu den Seelen der späteren Staatsmänner - einen Übergang, könnte man sagen, von einem Idealismus zu einem zunächst ziemlich äußerlichen Realismus. Ich kann die Dinge ja nur skizzieren.

Italien ging von Etappe zu Etappe. Bereits im Sommer 1871 konnte Viktor Emanuel in Rom einziehen. Was hat es ihm möglich gemacht? Die deutschen Siege über Frankreich! Francesco Crispi, ein italienischer Staatsmann der späteren Zeit, hat es selber gesagt, denn von ihm rührt der folgende Satz her: Italien ging nach Rom dank der deutschen Siege. - Frankreich hatte bei Solferino den ersten Anstoß dazu gegeben; daß aber Rom die Hauptstadt des Königreichs Italien wurde, ist auf die deutschen Siege über Frankreich zurückzuführen. Und nun entwickelt sich ein merkwürdiges Verhältnis zwischen Italien und Frankreich. Es ist interessant zu sehen, wie Italien in dem Maße, in dem es seine Einheit konsolidierte, in ein merkwürdiges Verhältnis zu Frankreich kam: Es wurde zugleich Gegner und Verbündeter. Und nun kommt in Betracht, daß Italien Staatsmänner hatte, die - das ist die reine Wahrheit - sehr viel auf die Tatsache gaben, daß Italien als Staatsgefüge von außen zusammengefügt worden ist und daß der letzte große Schritt zur Einheit eigentlich Deutschland zu verdanken ist. Diese Staatsmänner, die waren da. Sie sahen auch, daß dazumal ein mögliches Zusammengehen mit Frankreich für Italien nicht fruchtbar sein konnte. Aber dieser einen Strömung widersprach eine andere — diejenige, welche allmählich heraufkam und namentlich vom Jahre 1876 an stark wurde; es widersprach dieser ersten Strömung diejenige der frankophilen demokratisch-linken Partei. Und nun schaukelte dieses Staatswesen sozusagen zwischen seinem gefühlsmäßigen Hinneigen zu Frankreich und seinem mehr praktischen Hinneigen zu Mitteleuropa. Aber das Merkwürdige war, daß in alldem, was sich da ausbildete, die Sache immer so lag, daß die praktische Ausrichtung nach Mitteleuropa zum Ausschlaggebenden wurde - dasjenige, was real vorlag.

Nun kam eine neue Wendung in die ganze Sache, als Frankreich sich nach Tunis hinüber ausbreitete - Tunis hatte man ja immer als einen Ort betrachtet, der selbstverständlich zu Italien gehört. Nun fing Frankreich an, sich dort auszubreiten. Und da bekam die praktische Richtung in Italien Oberwasser - jene Richtung, welche sich nunmehr an Mitteleuropa anlehnte. Es ist zum Beispiel interessant, daß bei dem Berliner Kongreß der italienische Unterhändler fragte, warum Bismarck Frankreich das Anerbieten mache, sich ruhig in Afrika auszubreiten, ob er denn durchaus Italien in einen Krieg mit Frankreich verwickeln wolle. Jedenfalls war Italien für die damaligen italienischen Staatsmänner dadurch auf Deutschland angewiesen, und wie Bismarck das berühmte Wort gesprochen hat: Der Weg zu Deutschland führt über Wien -, so war Italien auch auf Österreich verwiesen, weshalb die alte Erbfeindschaft ad acta gelegt werden mußte, die Österreich als sein tragisches Geschick, möchte ich sagen, übernommen hatte. Denn mit alldem, was die Republik Venedig gemacht hatte, war eigentlich im Grunde genommen dasjenige aus Italien hinausgedrängt worden, was dann zu Deutschland ging; Österreich aber mußte das dann eben übernehmen - den Zug, der von Norden kam. Unter dem Einflusse des französischen Vorgehens in Nordafrika mußte die frankophile Richtung zurückstehen, und der Anschluß an Mitteleuropa wurde damals für Italien eine Selbstverständlichkeit.

Sie wissen, der Dreibund kam zustande - ich erwähne diese Dinge nur skizzenhaft, weil es ja schließlich nicht meine Aufgabe ist, Politik zu betreiben, aber gewisse Dinge muß man schon wissen, und sie werden heute leider viel zu wenig gewußt -, Sie wissen, 1882 kam der sogenannte Dreibund zustande. Und gewisse Menschen werden diesen Dreibund immer falsch beurteilen, weil sie sich nicht daran gewöhnen können, gültige Begriffe bei diesen Dingen anzuwenden. Es gibt ja wirklich Leute, die zum Beispiel die heutigen schmerzlichen Kriegsereignisse dem Dreibund zuschreiben und nicht dem sogenannten Dreiverband, der «Entente cordiale» oder wie das auch immer genannt wird. Aber sehen Sie, in solchen Dingen verwendet man nicht immer gültige Begriffe; überall sonst fragt man bei einem Ding, das zu etwas führen soll, ob es wirklich dazu führt und wie lange es taugt. Nun ist von denen, die am Dreibund beteiligt waren, immer gesagt worden, er sei zur Erhaltung des Friedens gemacht worden. Und er hat viele Jahrzehnte dazu getaugt, den Frieden zu erhalten, das heißt, er hat durch Jahrzehnte hindurch das gebracht, was man behauptete, wozu er bestimmt sei. Dann ist der Dreiverband gegründet worden, von dem man auch sagte «zur Erhaltung des Friedens». Aber es hat kein Jahrzehnt gebraucht - und der Friede war weg! Jedes andere Ding in der Welt, meine lieben Freunde, würde man nach dem beurteilen, was es hervorbringt; nur just in diesen Dingen läßt man sich nicht dazu herbei, ein objektives Urteil zu fällen. Schon nach fünf Jahren wurde jene geheime Sache eingefädelt, die die Möglichkeit gibt, die Alchemie jener Kugeln und Bomben genauer zu studieren, die, wie ich Ihnen neulich in verschiedenen Zusammenhängen sagte, in Sarajevo gebraucht worden sind, um jenes Attentat zustande zu bringen. Denn jenes Attentat vom Juni 1914, das hat ja [fast] nicht mißglücken können - sollten die einen Kugeln versagen, so sollten andere treffen! Es war dazumal wirklich in reichlichstem Maße dafür gesorgt, daß, selbst wenn das eine hätte versagen sollen, das andere nicht mißlungen wäre. Es war ein so wohldurchdachtes, man möchte sagen großangelegtes Attentat, wie überhaupt noch keines in der Weltgeschichte da war. Wenn man gewissermaßen die Alchemie dieser Kugeln studiert, so kommt man dazu, diese Dinge, die wir jetzt auf Wunsch unserer Freunde eben anführen, ein wenig zu durchschauen. Darauf werde ich noch zurückkommen.

Es wurde nämlich schon nach fünf Jahren in das ganze Dreibundverhältnis von Mitteleuropa etwas hineingemischt, das man so bezeichnen kann: Es ist ein gewisser Zusammenhang geschaffen worden zwischen jedem Ereignis, das in Italien vorgeht, und jedem Ereignis, das auf dem Balkan vorgeht. Es wurde danach gestrebt, daß nichts auf dem Balkan vorgehen könne, ohne daß irgend etwas Entsprechendes in Italien geschehe. Und es sollten die Volksleidenschaften so zusammenspielen, daß niemals eine einseitige Handlung vorgehen könne da oder dort, sondern daß da immer parallel gefühlt und gedacht werde. Es war ein inniger Zusammenhang zwischen den verschiedenen Impulsen auf der apenninischen und auf der Balkanhalbinsel durch die ganzen Jahrzehnte hindurch. Manchmal tritt einem eine solche Sache ungemein symbolisch entgegen - symbolisch schön, in bezug auf die Theorie schön, so wie der Arzt einen besonders schweren Krankheitsfall, weil er ihm die Gelegenheit zu einer guten Operation gibt, einen «schönen Fall» nennt, aber dieser braucht deshalb überhaupt nicht schön zu sein.

Wir waren einmal in Italien und besuchten in Rom einen Mann, der wirklich ein sehr netter, lieber Mensch war und ein sehr freundlicher Herr - er ist jetzt schon tot. Er führte uns in seinen Salon, und wir fanden bei diesem Herrn im Salon an ganz hervorragender Stelle die beiden Bilder von Draga Mašin und Alexander Obrenovič, groß, mit eigenhändigen Widmungen der betreffenden Persönlichkeiten. Dieser Mann, um den es sich da handelte, war nicht nur ein ganz berühmter Professor, sondern er war auch einer der Arrangeure der sogenannten lateinischen Liga, [der «Lega Nazionale»], die sich mit den Vorbereitungen für die Abtrennung Südtirols und Triests von Österreich und ihrer Angliederung an Italien befaßt. Nun, meine lieben Freunde, ich will selbstverständlich nicht aus einem so unbedeutenden Erlebnis große Schlüsse ziehen, aber ich muß doch sagen: Symbolisch bedeutsam ist es, daß jemand, der eine lateinische Liga arrangiert, der mit dieser lateinischen Liga vorzugsweise auch die Studenten der Universität Innsbruck revolutioniert - ich urteile nicht, ich kritisiere nicht, sondern ich erzähle nur -, daß dieser Mann in seinem Salon, also da, wo es jeder sehen soll, die Bilder von Alexander Obrenovič und Draga Ma$in mit eigenhändigen Widmungen hängen hat. Da dieses in der Zeit war, in der mir sehr wohl die geheimnisvollen Fäden bekannt waren, die zwischen Rom und Belgrad bestehen, machte es auf mich eben einen gewissen symptomatischen Eindruck, denn man wird schon durch sein Karma mit dem in der Welt zusammengeführt, was einem wichtig ist, und wenn man die Dinge anzuschauen vermag in der rechten Weise und sie zu durchschauen vermag, dann sieht man schon, daß einem das Karma an die Stelle hinführt, wo man dasjenige zu «riechen» hat, was man «riechen» soll für seine Erkenntnis.

Nun verhielt es sich so, daß im Jahr 1888 — es war eines der Jahre, die ebensogut wie das Jahr 1914 zum Weltkrieg hätten führen können —, daß im Jahr 1888 dadurch, daß Crispi zum Dreibund hielt, diese Krise verhindert worden ist. Diese Krise ist also dadurch verhindert worden, daß Crispi, der italienische Ministerpräsident, zum Dreibund hielt. Aber er hielt zum Dreibund nur aus dem Grunde, weil Frankreich in Nordafrika vorrückte und sich dort ausbreitete. Nun betrieb Frankreich damals eine Politik, von der Frankreich selber sagte, man wolle Italien, das sich von Frankreich abzuwenden beginne, «durch Hunger wiedererobern», das heißt, man versuchte eine Art von Handelskrieg gegen Italien zu führen - den berühmten Handelskrieg, der ja dazumal wirklich eine große Rolle spielte. Und die Folge dieses Handelskrieges war, daß die praktischen Bande gerade zu Mitteleuropa immer enger geknüpft wurden. Und ich tue vielleicht gut, wenn ich dabei nicht irgendein Urteil aus Deutschland anführe, sondern das Urteil eines Franzosen, der sagte, das moderne Italien sei eine wirtschaftliche Organisation Deutschlands.

Das heißt also - das ist ja oftmals betont worden, nicht nur von Deutschen, sondern auch von andern -, vor der Gefahr, von Frankreich durch Hunger erobert zu werden, was ja nicht gerade eine angenehme Sache ist, wurde Italien dadurch gerettet, daß es in innigere wirtschaftliche Beziehung zu Deutschland trat. Das alles wirkte zusammen, um die Krise am Ende der achtziger Jahre in friedlichem Sinne zu lösen. Diese Krise Ende der achtziger Jahre in ihren Einzelheiten zu studieren, ist außerordentlich interessant, und zwar aus dem Grunde interessant, weil das Studium dieser Einzelheiten gerade demjenigen etwas Besonderes gibt, der geneigt ist, auf Zusammenhänge zu schauen und sich nicht blenden zu lassen. Ich habe es gemacht, und es ist außerordentlich interessant, es zu machen. Es geschahen im Jahre 1888 Ereignisse, bei denen ich folgendes gemacht habe: Ich bin hergegangen und habe für alles dasjenige, was dazumal 1888 geschehen ist, skizzenhaft eingesetzt «1914» - anstelle von «1888». Es ist dasselbe, genau dasselbe, meine lieben Freunde! So wie 1914 die große Pressehetze losgegangen ist, die von Petersburg inspiriert war und nach Deutschland herübergriff, geradeso war es 1888. So wie 1914 ein Konflikt hervorgerufen werden sollte zwischen Deutschland und Österreich, so dazumal 1888. Kurz, in allen Einzelheiten sind die Dinge dieselben. Und interessant ist es, daß ich verschiedenen Leuten eine Rede vorlesen konnte, die dazumal im Jahre 1888 gehalten worden ist, in der ich nur statt «1888» fingiert «1914» eingesetzt habe, und jeder hat geglaubt, das, was dazumal im Jahre 1888 gesagt worden ist, beziehe sich auf 1914! Meine lieben Freunde, wenn solche Dinge möglich sind, dann wird man doch nicht von Zufälligkeiten sprechen, sondern man wird davon sprechen, daß da treibende Kräfte am Werke sind und daß System darin ist.

Nun, 1888 ging die Sache vorüber aus den Gründen, die ich angeführt habe. Dann aber wurden die Verhältnisse noch schwieriger. Die Verhältnisse wurden insbesondere deshalb so schwierig, weil das ganze Verhältnis der apenninischen Halbinsel zu Mitteleuropa wirklich einen solchen Charakter annahm - es ist psychologisch interessant, gerade für den Geistesforscher ist es psychologisch interessant, diese Dinge zu studieren -, es nahm wirklich den Charakter an, daß Italien, das politische Italien, so behandelt werden mußte, wie manche Dame - verzeihen Sie, es sind nur die hysterischen gemeint. Es sind unglaubliche Dinge, die sich entwickelten, namentlich dadurch, daß immer mehr und mehr in Europa das Urteil aufkam und propagiert wurde: Österreich muß zerfallen. - Ich kritisiere diese Dinge nicht, ich erzähle nur.

In welcher Weise dieses Urteil in Europa propagiert wurde, davon können Sie sich ja überzeugen, wenn Sie Publikationen lesen wie jene von Loiseau, Chéradame und so weiter - Bücher, die durchaus davon handeln, wie Österreich in den nächsten Zeiten zerteilt werden wird. Und solche Urteile wie diejenigen von Loiseau und Chéradame wurden hineingeworfen in dasjenige, was da unten im Süden glimmte. Es war wirklich nicht leicht, unter diesen Umständen das zu treiben, was oftmals Politik genannt wird, denn sehen Sie, in Italien wurde zum Beispiel - ich will das nicht kritisieren, ich will gar nicht einmal im geringsten pro oder contra sprechen, sondern nur erzählen - sogar der Oberdank gefeiert, der ein Attentat auf den Kaiser Franz Joseph geplant hatte. Dagegen durfte in Wien in einer Ausstellung, die der Herzog der Abruzzen besuchen wollte, ein Bild nicht die «Seeschlacht bei Lissa» heißen - Österreich hatte sie nämlich gewonnen -, sondern es wurde einfach darauf geschrieben «Eine Seeschlacht», damit der Herzog der Abruzzen nicht beleidigt wurde, wenn er nach Wien in die Ausstellung kam. Das ist aber nur ein Beispiel für unzählige Beispiele - und das tat man tatsächlich. Ich kritisiere das nicht, aber ich frage nach der Gegenseitigkeit; ich frage, ob sich irgend jemand in Italien zu der Rücksicht herbeigelassen hätte, bei einer gewonnenen Seeschlacht den Namen wegzulassen - in Wien hat man es allerdings getan. Man mag das sogar falsch finden von einem gewissen Gesichtspunkte aus, aber ich frage nach der Gegenseitigkeit. Und das sei doch gesagt, um ein wenig die Stimmungen zu charakterisieren, denn auf solche Stimmungen kommt es an, wenn nun solch eine Strömung einzugreifen hat wie diejenige, die vom «Grand Orient de France» kam, wenn nun also okkulte Impulse ins Spiel gebracht werden.

Und es werden schon, meine lieben Freunde, gewisse Dinge, um die sich die Menschheit bisher nicht gekümmert hat, zu solchen werden müssen, um die sich die Menschheit kümmert, denn die «massoni» sind nicht so, daß sie nicht sehen, was da ist, sondern sie gehen — ebenso wie die anderen okkulten Bruderschaften - darauf aus, die Kräfte, die da sind, ins Spiel zu bringen. Sie wissen, daß da und dort Impulse vorhanden sind und wie man sie so benützen muß. Und wenn man auf der einen Seite, auf der apenninischen, eine gewisse Strömung hat und auf dem Balkan eine andere, dann müssen diese Strömungen in der entsprechenden Weise benützt werden, und dann kann man schon im rechten Augenblick, das heißt in dem für diese Leute rechten Augenblick, dieses oder jenes tun.

Das also sei eine Vorbereitung für die alchimistische Betrachtung, von der ich Ihnen gesprochen habe und die uns dann etwas weiterführen wird. Ich bitte Sie, durchaus zu beachten, daß ich nicht anders kann, wenn ich den Wünschen unserer Freunde entsprechen soll, als einiges von dem, was in der Gegenwart spielt, zu erwähnen in Anknüpfung an Dinge, die es eben gibt, wenn auch vielleicht nicht jeder damit einverstanden ist, daß solche Dinge an die Oberfläche gebracht werden. Allein, es ist meine Überzeugung, meine lieben Freunde: Gerade darin, daß man vor diesen Dingen die Augen zudrückt und über das, was vorgeht, aus möglichst unsachlichen Untergründen heraus redet, liegt einer der Hauptgründe, daß solch Schmerzliches, wie es jetzt der Fall ist, über die Welt hinziehen kann, denn selbst diesen großen Dingen gegenüber sollte jeder mit der Selbsterkenntnis anfangen. Und ein Stück Selbsterkenntnis ist schon dies, daß man weiß: In dem Augenblicke, wo man sagt, solche Dinge gingen einen nichts an, man wolle nur von okkulten Dingen hören, fördert man, wenn auch zunächst nur im kleinen, jene Entwicklung, die, aus vielen einzelnen Gliedern [zu einer Kette] zusammengefügt und summiert, zu solchen Dingen führt, wie wir sie heute erleben. Denn okkult ist nicht nur das, was sich auf die höheren Welten bezieht - das ist ja gewiß zunächst für alle Menschen okkult -, aber okkult, meine lieben Freunde, ist für viele Menschen auch schon das, was auf dem physischen Plan geschieht. Und man möchte wünschen, daß manches Okkulte auf diesem Gebiet offenbar würde, denn daß so vieles für so viele, die dann doch urteilen, okkult bleibt, das bildet mit eine der Quellen für das Elend, das wir erleben.

Morgen werden wir uns, wenn niemand etwas dagegen hat, wieder um fünf Uhr treffen.

Fifth Lecture

My dear friends! If we were not an association that has to consider all things from the standpoint of knowledge, and indeed of profound spiritual knowledge, it would be self-evident that I should now adhere to the considerations that many of you have been making for several days. It is also self-evident, I believe, that every soul that is serious and sincere about human salvation must look forward with anxious expectation to what will happen in the next few days.

I believe it is also self-evident that every soul who is serious and sincere about the welfare of humanity must look forward with anxious anticipation to what will happen in the coming days, for it is the facts that will decide whether certain voices from what we have called the periphery, the circle around us, are capable of reflect on themselves to such an extent that the whole of humanity, including the humanity of the future, cannot reasonably be expected to believe that peace for humanity is desired, that people are fighting for peace, if they do not seize the opportunity to achieve this peace—and to achieve it in a relatively short time. No one would be obliged, not even for appearances' sake—I say for appearances' sake—to believe in a shred of sincerity in all the declamations about peace or even the rights of peoples if things were to proceed as they appear to be proceeding according to the newspapers, which, of course, are no longer of any interest to serious observers today. But the world will have opportunity to hear more in the near future, and it will have to decide either to accept with full awareness the declarations of a desire for peace as false and untruthful and continue to regard them as significant in some way, or to turn to the truth. But we, my dear friends, stand on the ground of knowledge, and therefore we need not interrupt these reflections. We seek the truth, and the truth must in all cases be what is to be sought. Therefore, it can never seriously be harmful or have a harmful effect.

I would now like to present to you some thoughts that may enable us to justify our judgment in some respects. I would like — and you will have gathered this from the various remarks I have made — not to influence anyone's point of view or judgment in the slightest, but it is precisely a matter of calmly looking at the facts of the physical plane as well as the facts and impulses of the spiritual world. I spoke to you some time ago about the fact that the question of necessity in world events must certainly be considered, even in relation to the most painful events. But anthroposophy will never make us fatalists; it will never lead us to speak of necessity in such a way that we simply say that we must submit to these necessities as to a fate. One may well ask: Did these painful events that have occurred have to happen? Even if one were to feel compelled to say, hypothetically, that yes, they were necessary, even in that case it cannot be a matter of simply resigning oneself fatalistically to this necessity. Let me first clarify what I mean by this with a comparison.

Let us assume that two people are arguing about what next year's harvest will be like in a certain area. Well, someone could come along and say: This harvest depends on the necessities of nature; we are dealing with an external necessity. And he could very nicely list all the necessities: the weather and other conditions that are more or less independent of human will. Fine, good! But the other person could say: You're right, that may all be true, but the main thing is to consider the question as practically as it requires our practical cooperation. And here it is much less important to me to talk about the weather or this or that, but rather that I, who am involved and want to be involved in next year's harvest, sow the best seeds I can find. And whatever the other factors may be, it is up to me to sow the best seeds, and I will strive to do so. The first man may be a fatalist, the second will not deny the basis for his fatalism, but he will do everything he can to sow the right seeds. And so it is for every person who wants to be reasonable: above all, it is a matter of finding the opportunity to sow the right seeds.

Now, of course, for the spiritual development of humanity, the phrase “sowing the right seeds” means something much more complicated than the comparison I have just given, for it is not a matter of merely asserting a few abstract principles, but of recognizing in the right way, from the conditions of human development, what is necessary for this human development at the present moment. Whatever the weather may be next year, whatever obstacles or unfavorable conditions may arise, if the second person does not sow his seed, there will certainly be no harvest, not even a poor one! And so it is necessary to realize that certain conditions must be created in the present, conditions against which the greatest, the vast majority of people still resist today — conditions that must be incorporated into human development so that a prosperous, salutary development can take place in the future. And it is necessary to realize that, above all, humanity is currently in such a phase of development that, within certain limits, it is left to itself to deal with its errors.

This was not the case in earlier times, my dear friends — in earlier times, up until the fifth post-Atlantean period, when the people of Earth, at least for the most part, were led to become fully conscious of their freedom; before that, divine-spiritual powers intervened directly in the development of the earth, and they intervened in such a way that this intervention of the divine-spiritual powers was also felt by human beings. This was clearly perceptible. And today it is important to point out to humanity the necessity of coming to certain insights, above all of coming to a healthy judgment about certain things, a judgment that is in harmony with the conditions of human development. The fact that there is resistance to this judgment is one of the deeper causes of the painful events of the present.

Certainly, we will also have to discuss the question of why humanity did not turn to more spiritual tendencies a century ago, for if it had done so, the painful situation we find ourselves in today would certainly not have arisen. But let us postpone this question for today and perhaps take it up again tomorrow or the day after. Above all, we want to hold fast to the fact that the painful events have arisen largely from the rejection of the connection with the spiritual world. One may therefore call the events of today the karma of materialism, but one must not take this word “karma of materialism” as a mere phrase; one must understand it in the right way. Insights that would be deeply necessary have only appeared sporadically, here and there, in the times we have more or less already lived through, that is, in the last decades of the 19th century and the first decades of the 20th century. Certainly, some insights—and insights are very important—have been thrown into humanity, and attempts have been made to throw them into humanity in such a way that a larger number of people could eventually have been grasped by them. But at present — for reasons that can be mentioned later — there is still an enormous resistance in humanity to any possible higher insight based on a spiritual foundation.

Years ago, a certain book was published. You may say: A book was published? Well, many books are published, what significance does that have? At most, it can have theoretical significance when a book is published — it can serve as instruction — because the salvation of the world cannot depend on people reading this or that. Nevertheless, much more depends on whether certain ideas, certain insights spread than one might think. If you review in your soul what I have said in the last two or three lectures, you will be able to admit this yourself. A book, I said, has been published, and the author of this book is Brooks Adams; it was published years ago in America. At the time, this book seemed to me to be one of the most significant manifestations of recent human insight, even though the way in which it was sent out into the world was spoiled by the fact that one of the greatest phrase-mongers of the present day, namely former President Roosevelt, wrote the preface to it. But the fact remains that the ideas in Brooks Adams' book could have had an enlightening effect in the broadest sense. For European intellectual life, it was also significant that the German translation of Brooks Adams' book was published by a publishing house known to be serving very specific intellectual movements—intellectual movements that are decidedly hostile and detrimental to ours, the anthroposophical movement. But that is not the point. What is important is to have a sense that it matters when, I would say, certain ideas are put out into the world under such a banner. For there is a difference between a book being published, say, by Cotta's publishing house — a respected, distinguished publishing house that simply publishes books — and a book like the one mentioned above being published by a publishing house that otherwise publishes writings in the service of a very special society. There is a big difference between dealing with literature and dealing with deliberate impulses – there is a big difference!

So what does this book by Brooks Adams contain? I will just outline the main ideas for you. The main ideas are developed in a, I would even say amateurish way – insofar as their significance could be recognized in America – in a very general and abstract manner. But first of all, it is important to know that someone is, in a sense, tentatively letting such a “bird fly” from one place. The ideas developed in this book are roughly as follows: There are different peoples in the world who have been developing over long periods of time. One can trace the rise and fall of these peoples: they are born, they go through infancy, a period of youth, a period of maturity, old age, and then they perish again. Of course, this is not a profound truth, but only a skeleton, but what Brooks Adams develops as laws for this development of peoples is already of some significance. He says: One can observe that peoples, as a rule, in their youth, when they are still youthful peoples, necessarily develop two related dispositions. If one wants to go into ideas such as those of Brooks Adams at all, one must of course strictly separate peoples as such from the individual human beings who belong to them, and one must not confuse the concept of the state with that of the people.

Brooks Adams thus attributes certain characteristics to a very specific period in the development of peoples, and in his view these characteristics belong together. He says: Certain peoples in their youth have, first of all, a predisposition to imagination, that is, they have the ability to form ideas that are primarily drawn from within, that owe their origin to productive imagination—not to reflection, not to what we today call science, but to the creative inner power of human beings. Such peoples, Brooks Adams believes – I am only quoting here – have another characteristic that is necessarily connected with this, namely that these peoples are warlike. And in these peoples of an imaginative nature, the characteristics of imagination and warlike tendencies are inseparable. He considers this to be a natural law of the intellectual life of these peoples. Thus, for him, there is initially a type of people: the imaginative and warlike peoples.

However, he believes there is another type of people. These are people in whom imagination no longer predominates, but has become what we call cool, scientific judgment. Such people, who have cool, scientific judgment, are by their very nature not warlike, but industrial and commercial. And these two characteristics—not of individuals, but of peoples—these two characteristics, insofar as they appear as characteristics of peoples, belong together: scientifically and commercially, after all, industry is only the basis of commerce. So on the one hand, scientific-commercial, on the other, imaginative-warlike.

I do not wish to criticize these ideas for the time being, but I would just like to mention that here, albeit in an amateurish way, a judgment is being made that “fluttered” over from America years ago, so to speak, and which says: Beware of believing that you can mold humanity, or, let us say, human boots, to fit any mold. Do not believe that you can establish arbitrary ideals. Bear in mind that one can only speak of what is grounded in evolution, and that one cannot expect a people such as the Slavs, who have an imaginative character, to be non-warlike. Anyone who reads Brooks Adams' book carefully will be particularly struck by the last example.

And one should not judge by outward appearances, but by inner values, by inner affinities. The book is amateurish for the simple reason, my dear friends, that such a realization, if it is expressed at all, can only be expressed on the basis of spiritual insights. But as long as one does not have spiritual insights, judgments about the evolution of humanity, in which spiritual powers are at work, will of course always be one-sided, because one will exclude above all one great truth—the great truth that one stands within the Maya insofar as one has to deal with events on the physical plane, but also with the will of human beings. Now, my dear friends, as soon as one does not treat Maya as Maya, one must fall into error; one must always fall into error if one treats Maya as a reality. And one treats Maya as a reality mostly by not paying proper attention to becoming within Maya and to that which is similar to becoming. Why?

Well, wouldn't it be wonderful if it weren't nonsense to have spring all the time, to have plants always in bloom, to have life always sprouting and budding? And someone might say: Why didn't the creators of the world arrange things so that there is always sprouting, budding life? Why do the beautiful tulips, lilies, and roses have to wither and rot? Very simple, isn't it? So that they can bloom again, that's why they have to wither and rot! Insofar as we are on the physical plane, we must be clear that one cannot exist without the other, indeed, that one exists for the sake of the other, and that Goethe's statement has a profound truth, that nature created death in order to have much life. Because the physical world is Maya, as long as one remains within the physical world, there is no balance, but only at the moment when one can rise from the physical to the spiritual world. Then, however, this balance will appear different from what one believes as long as one considers the physical world to be reality. This means that it is necessary to familiarize oneself with the laws of Maya and to learn that within Maya, balance cannot be found anywhere, neither through humans nor through other beings, unless that which lies outside Maya, that which lies in spiritual reality, is woven into Maya.

Therefore, it is always a matter of getting to know the Maya as Maya—getting to know how things behave within the Maya, where blossoming, sprouting, and sprouting must be accompanied by withering. Everyone will readily admit this when it comes to nature; they are inclined to acknowledge this fact because it is so obvious in nature. So it will be easy to convince everyone that in the summer or fall of 1917, only what was sown in the corresponding sowing period of the previous year can ripen into fruit. If bad seeds have been sown, only bad fruit can be harvested—that is quite natural. And that is why people will be inclined to look at the sowing and, in this case, will not be so easily fooled by Maja as in other areas of human life where things appear clouded. For, you see, if at any time one points out in a similar way something that in the life of a people is the same as sowing bad seeds for the annual ripening of fruit, one immediately encounters prejudice. And these are roughly equivalent to what happens when I say to someone: Well, you shouldn't be surprised if you reap a poor harvest today, because look at what you sowed — and he immediately replies: What? That's what I sowed, and if you have something to say about last year's sowing, then you're hitting a nerve. But I don't want to hurt him, because he may be completely innocent of sowing the seeds. It is not a matter of hurting anyone personally, but of objectively stating the facts. It is not my business to judge the connection between him and his sowing — that is his business, and I leave it entirely to him. But for the sake of objective knowledge, it may be necessary to examine the sowing carefully and look at what it actually is. If one remains objective, it may also be of benefit to the person who was involved in the sowing, provided that someone else has not, how shall I put it? — “pulled over the coarse” by someone else; he may even be able to derive considerable benefit from it if the connection between the harvest and the sowing is made clear to him. I would just like to say this to point out that it is important to direct one's thoughts in the right direction and to search in the right way.

And now, having said this, I would like to mention something else — for two different reasons, as you will see in a moment or a little later. In the course of my recent reflections, I have drawn attention to a king of England who played a major role for England in terms of religious development in the field of Maya — precisely in the field of Maya: Henry VIII. You know, he had a lot of practice in getting rid of his wives—he had accumulated a large number of them. But he also had, well, let's say the courage to break away from the Pope because the Pope did not want to dissolve one of his marriages. And for this reason, because the Pope did not want to dissolve one of his marriages, Henry VIII had the courage to give the whole of England, as far as it depended on him, a new religion. Well, we have already talked about that.

Now, during the reign of Henry VIII—as I have already pointed out—there lived Thomas More, the great and important Thomas More. He was a man who, at that time—Thomas More lived at the turn of the 15th to the 16th century—raised spirituality to the level at which we also find, for example, the wonderful Pico della Mirandola and other similar important figures. This Thomas More was therefore an enlightened spirit. Despite being an enlightened spirit, he became Chancellor to Henry VIII, and he did not despise Henry VIII. I will prove to you in a moment that he did not despise Henry VIII so readily, because he was already a spirit who, out of his instinct—out of his enlightened instinct—was able to take Maja as Maja. Now, Thomas More was at the same time a pious man like Pico della Mirandola, a sincerely pious man, not a pious man like Henry VII, nor like the Pope, but a sincere, seriously pious man. And from his point of view, he also rejected all attempts at reform and all reformist impulses that had already begun to emerge at that time. Thomas More was, in a certain sense, a faithful son of the Catholic Church, and he was not inclined to go along with the king, even if he would have received all honors; he was not inclined to go along, even though he had become chancellor. Nevertheless, he was not inclined to simply join another religion because Henry VIII wanted another wife. For this reason, he was not only deposed, but also sentenced to death. And the records of this trial, in which he was sentenced to death, are extremely interesting and, my dear friends, very indicative of the times. When one reads the court ruling condemning Thomas More to death, it has a strange wording—a truly strange wording; this wording corresponds to something else to the extent that one carries out such a thing.

Most of you will know, because it has long been written in secular books, that in the common Masonic orders, advancement through the degrees is connected with certain formulas, and that these formulas also contain the manner of death that will befall those who do not keep the corresponding secret of that degree. He is told that under certain circumstances he will die a terrible death, for example, that his body will be cut open and his ashes scattered to the four winds, to all four corners of the world. As I said, these things have already become the subject of numerous profane writings. The sentence passed on Thomas More is entirely consistent with a certain degree formula: he was to be put to death in an inhuman manner. But that was not enough; they also wanted to cut his body into as many pieces as there are corners of the world and scatter the pieces to the different corners of the world. To a certain extent, the sentence was carried out.

Now consider that with this event – Thomas More was born in the second half of the 15th century and died in the first half of the 16th century – we are at the beginning of the fifth post-Atlantean period. But the question, my dear friends, must be allowed: Did Thomas More do nothing else but simply refuse to swear the oath of supremacy, that is, did he merely refuse to recognize that the English Church was now to be independent of the Pope and accept what Henry VIII decreed? Did he not do anything else? Let us now consider his most significant deed – a deed that even today can be of the utmost importance to those who properly consider it. Thomas More wrote the book “Utopia: A utopia, or the ideal city,” about the best form of government and the new island of Utopia. The main part of this book deals with the institutions of the island of Utopia, that is, the country “nowhere,” one might say, the “land of nowhere.” But anyone who reads Thomas More's book in the right spirit will see that Thomas More is much more concerned with “Utopia” than with any country in the external physical reality. Of course, if one is foolish enough to assume that a man like Thomas More wrote his “Utopia” simply to compose something out of his imagination—in other words, if one talks about utopians as those who think themselves particularly clever, then Thomas More cannot be counted among the utopians, for he did not, of course, want to present people with just any fantasy construct, but rather—as was possible in his time—he wanted to say much more with such a thing. The main part of the book is about “Utopia,” but the book has an introduction, and this introduction contains a great deal of variety; it also contains, I would say, explanations as to why Thomas More wrote the book about the island of Utopia. In it, he says roughly the following. He says – and this is an important passage that I would like to draw your attention to so that you can see that he did not despise Henry VII – he begins as follows:

Henry VIII, the invincible king of England, a prince of rare and superior spirit, had not long ago had a dispute of some importance with the illustrious Charles, Prince of Castile. I was then sent as ambassador to Flanders with the mission of settling these matters and, if possible, bringing them to a satisfactory conclusion.

Well, on this occasion, while he is sent to Flanders as an envoy on behalf of Henry VIII, whom he calls an enlightened and great king, he meets a man whom he finds, as he says, extraordinarily clever and intellectually remarkable, so that he [that is, his friend] asks the man: “Yes, if you know so many excellent things and can judge them correctly, as is the case with you, why do you not put your insights at the service of this or that prince?” Thomas More believes that those who serve a prince are mostly not very enlightened people and that an extraordinary amount of good and beneficial things could happen in the world if such enlightened people were to serve princes. To which the man replies: That would be of no use, because if I were to put forward my views in any ministry, I would not make the others any wiser, but they would very soon throw me out—it is not told in these words, but that is really what it says—I would be of no use if I did that. And to confirm, as it were, that this man actually lived, whom he allegedly does not agree with, Thomas More recounts the following. He says: I then met this man in a group of people, there were all sorts of people there, and this man told them how he had once tried to develop his views in another group.

This is not merely an introduction to “Utopia,” but rather—and this is the curious thing—Thomas More wants to use it to criticize England at that time, that is, England at the turn of the 15th century. The English chancellor wants to criticize England. Anyone who thinks like Thomas More is not offering a critique of an abstraction when he speaks of England, because he knows that the English people are something different from those who come to mind when one speaks of the configuration of the English state—he knows this very well. And he knows that this state is not a mere abstraction, but that it is made up of individuals; he knows that one does not really criticize the English people when one criticizes the actions of these individuals, on whose configurations, however, everything depends that matters when one speaks of the English state. Thomas More therefore takes the best, the most concrete approach possible, because it is of course not a concrete but merely a nonsensical approach to say: England is like this, Germany is like that, Italy is like this and so on – because in reality, this is actually talking about nothing.

Now he has this man, who, as I said, was a clever, enlightened person, meet in a larger society with another man who was an “excellent” lawyer—that is, what the world calls an excellent lawyer—and he has these two, the intelligent man and the man who is excellent in the eyes of the world, engage in a discussion about English jurisprudence. Now, English jurisprudence was not yet what it is today, but that does not matter—we are, after all, at the beginning of the fifth post-Atlantean period. The clever man thought that it was extremely foolish to treat thieves the way they were treated in England at that time. He did not think it was particularly clever at all. In fact, he did not think the whole way of thinking about theft or similar things was particularly clever; the man who had seen Utopia and later described it did not find the views that prevailed at the time on how to behave towards a thief, for example, to be wise at all, because he believed that one should first and foremost investigate where his motives came from. To the “distinguished” lawyer, this was of course completely incomprehensible. But now let us take a closer look at the arguments of this clever man—not the “distinguished” man. This clever man says:

One day I was dining with this prelate. By chance, I met a layman there who was, however, renowned as a great legal expert. This man, for reasons I do not know, showered praise on the strict justice meted out to thieves. With great satisfaction, he recounted how they were hanged here and there, twenty at a time, on the same gallows. “And yet,” he added, “what a disgrace! Of all these scoundrels, hardly two or three escape the noose, and England supplies new ones from all sides.” With the same ease of speech that I had observed in the cardinal, I replied: ‘There is nothing in this that should surprise you.’

Now the wise man speaks.

"In this respect, death is a punishment as unjust as it is useless. It is too cruel to punish theft and too weak to prevent it. Simple theft does not deserve the gallows, and the most terrible punishment will not deter from stealing those for whom it is the only means of escaping starvation. In this respect, the justice system in England and many other countries resembles a bad teacher who prefers to beat his pupils rather than teach them. Thieves are subjected to the most terrible tortures. Would it not be better to secure the existence of all members of society so that no one would be forced into the necessity of first stealing and then being put to death?"

“Society takes care of that,” replied my legal expert, “industry and agriculture provide the people with plenty of means of subsistence, but there are creatures who prefer crime to work.” “Now you're where I wanted you!” I replied.

The wise man speaks again:

"I will not even mention those who return home covered with wounds from internal or external wars, although I would have good reason to do so. For how many soldiers lost one or more limbs in the service of the king and the fatherland in the Battle of Cornwallis or in the campaign against France! These unfortunate men had become too weak to continue their old trade and too old to learn a new one. But let us leave that aside; we do not always live in times of war. Let us turn our eyes to what is happening around us every day.

The most important cause of public misery is the excessive number of nobles who, like idle hornets, feed on the sweat and labor of their neighbors and let their lands be cultivated

by others, sucking their tenants dry in order to increase their revenues; they know no other economy. But when it comes to indulging themselves, they are wasteful to the point of madness, even if it means reducing themselves to beggary. No less lamentable is the fact that they have in their retinue whole crowds of idle servants who have learned nothing by which they might secure their existence.

When these servants fall ill or lose their master through death, they are dismissed, for it is preferable to feed idlers than the sick, and often the heir of the deceased is unable to keep the servants who have been left to him.

Now, unless they have the heart to steal, these people are exposed to starvation. Indeed, what else can they do? While searching for new lodgings, they wear away their health and their clothes; and when illness has emaciated them and time has clothed them in rags, one is afraid to take them into service. Even the peasants do not feel compelled to do so. They know very well that a man who has spent his youth in idleness and pleasure, who is accustomed only to carrying a sword and shield, looking down proudly on his neighbors and despising the whole world—they know very well that such a man is ill-suited to handling a spade and a hoe and to working faithfully in the service of a poor farmer for meager wages and scanty food.”

“It is precisely this class of people,” my opponent replied, “that the state must nurture and multiply with the greatest care. They have more courage and mental ability than craftsmen and farmers. They are taller and stronger, and when they join the army, it is from them that we can expect the most in battle.”

“In other words,” I replied, [...]

- so now the clever man comes again —

[...] “to ensure glory and success in arms, one must multiply thieves. For the latter, those idlers form an inexhaustible school, and when viewed in the light of day, rogues are not the worst soldiers, and soldiers are not the most cowardly rogues; there are many similarities between these two professions. Unfortunately, England is not alone in suffering from this social wound; it is almost inherent in all nations.

An even more dangerous plague is gnawing at the inner life of France. Every inch of land there is covered with troops, distributed and paid by the state in regiments. And this happens in times of peace—if one can call the pauses in which war is little more than a breath a pause. This sad system is justified on the same grounds that make it seem necessary to you to maintain myriads of idle servants. Certain fearful and sinister politicians have been of the opinion that the security of the state requires a numerous, strong army, constantly under arms and composed of veterans. They dare not entrust themselves to new recruits. One would almost think that they waged war only to teach soldiers drill and, as Sallust says, to prevent their hearts and hands from falling asleep through this great slaughter of men.

France is learning at its own expense the danger of feeding this kind of carnivorous animal. Nevertheless, it should only look to the Romans, the Carthaginians, and a host of other ancient peoples. What did these monstrous and ever-ready armies bring them? The devastation of their countries, the destruction of their cities, the downfall of their empire. Yes, if only it had been of any use to the French to drill their soldiers from infancy! But France's veterans have had to deal with England's new recruits, and I do not know whether they can boast of having often gained the upper hand. I will pass over this chapter; it might appear that I am seeking to flatter those who listen to me."

So said Chancellor Thomas More. It is clear that all one needs to do today is copy what this chancellor said at the time about the French armies, and one could fabricate the most beautiful sentences and present them to the English ministers to rail against “Prussian militarism.” Only we are at the beginning of the fifth post-Atlantic period, and perhaps the comparison of today's rhetoric with what was at the beginning of things back then might be unpleasant in certain respects!

Now, you see, Thomas More has a man speak—you may say, for my sake, that he has invented him—he has a man speak who tries to get to the bottom of things, and he tries to get to the bottom of things in a way that is unpleasant to some people, even if the things are only touched upon. But he goes further and says:

"Whichever way I look at the question, this countless mass of idle people seems to me to be of no use to the country, even in the event of war, which, incidentally, can always be avoided. Moreover, they are a real nuisance in times of peace, and peace deserves to be taken just as seriously as war.”

But the gentry and servants are not the only causes of the thefts that afflict you. There is another, which is peculiar to your island alone."

So says the man who comes from Utopia and who wants to teach his listeners something about the peculiarities of that state.

“And what is that peculiarity?” asked the cardinal.

So there was also someone who joined in the conversation.

“In the countless flocks of sheep that today cover the whole of England. These animals, which are so gentle and undemanding everywhere else, are so voracious and cruel among you that they even attack humans and chase them from the fields, houses, and villages.”

Indeed, throughout the kingdom, where the finest and most precious wool is gathered, one sees the nobles, the rich, and even very venerable abbots.

Indeed, in all parts of the kingdom where the finest and most precious wool is gathered, one sees the nobles, the rich, and even very venerable abbots rushing to dispute the terrain. Their rents, their privileges, the revenues from their lands are not enough for these poor people; they are not content to live in idleness and pleasure, a burden on the public and of no use to the state. For miles around, they alienate the soil from cultivation, turn it into pastures, tear down houses and villages, sparing only the churches—in order to obtain stables for their sheep. They turn the most inhabited and best cultivated places into wastelands. No doubt they fear that there are too many gardens and woods and that the wild animals will lack land.

Thus, a greedy glutton surrounds several thousand acres of land with a single ring wall; righteous country people are driven from their homes, some by fraud, others by violence, the luckiest by a chain of oppression and placards, forcing them to sell their possessions. And then these families, who are less rich than numerous, for agriculture requires many hands, wander across the fields, men and women, widows and orphans, fathers and mothers with small children. Weeping, the unfortunate flee the roof under which they were born, the soil that fed them, and do not know where to seek refuge. They sell what they can carry of their belongings for a pittance—items that are of little value in themselves. Once this meager source is exhausted, what remains for them? Theft and, later, outright hanging.

Perhaps they prefer to drag out their misery as beggars. But then there is no hesitation in throwing them into prison as vagrants and people without a home. And what is their crime? It consists of nothing more than not being able to find anyone who will give them work, even though they seek it most eagerly. Who will employ them? They know only how to cultivate the fields; so where there is no longer any thought of sowing or reaping, there is nothing for them to do. A single shepherd or cowherd is now sufficient to graze lands that formerly required several hundred poor people to cultivate.

Another consequence of this pernicious system is the very high price of food in several regions.

But that is not all. Since the proliferation of grazing lands, a pestilential disease has killed an incalculable number of sheep. It almost seems as if heaven wanted to punish the insatiable greed of their grabbers with this terrible mortality, which it would have turned more justly against their own heads. The price of wool has risen so high that the poor cloth workers can no longer afford to buy any. And so you have once again a mass of unemployed people. It cannot be denied that the number of sheep is growing daily at an extraordinary rate; but the price of sheep has nevertheless not fallen at all, because the wool trade, although not a legal monopoly, is in fact exclusively in the hands of a few rich collectors who are under no pressure to sell and therefore only sell at the greatest advantage.

Well, I will not read this passage any further, my dear friends; I will only remark that here you see the Chancellor Thomas More, the like-minded companion of Pico della Mirandola, exercising harsh criticism through the—for my sake fictitious—man who comes from Utopia, but criticism of something that existed at that time, something that really happened, for this really did happen: that over vast areas people were driven from their lands, that those who cultivated the soil with their hands were expelled and their lands turned into pastures for the sheep of the landowners, who in this way wanted to reap the full benefit of the wool. That it is necessary to intervene at this point, that there are people who drive people off their land and soil in order to use it for sheep flocks—Thomas More found it necessary to say this.

And those people, my dear friends, who objectively link effects to their causes, can now see on the physical plane how the present state of the English nation is intimately connected with what happened in the past and what Thomas More criticizes in this way. And if you investigate this with the means that are already available, my dear friends, you will find that the English people are not responsible for many things for which political England is very much responsible. But those who are responsible for political England are the successors and, to a certain extent, even the blood successors of those who are criticized here by Thomas More. There is a continuous development that goes back to that time. And if you consider such things, you will know and find that speeches such as those made by Lord Rosebery, which I quoted to you recently, contain the voices of those who at that time obtained their profits in this way. One must look everywhere for the objective connections.

Above all, however, one must insist on not being misunderstood in any way. What does it mean when someone reproaches you: You should be more sensitive, because the English must think this way or that way! That is not the point at all. The point is that certain things in our present life can be traced back to certain causes, and that these causes must be sought in the right places. The real descendants, the blood descendants of those who once drove people from their homes and farms, from their land, in order to keep flocks of sheep instead of leaving the fields to grow crops—no one has any reason to defend these people and their impulses simply because they are English. So, my dear friends, it is a matter of becoming a little familiar with the laws that we are actually dealing with, and of looking at what is real in the world, and not of prattling on about this nation being guilty of this or that.

Now that I have tried to show you a characteristic connection between something that is in the present and something that was in the past, I will move on to a completely different point, and then bring the individual points together. I will present you with some facts, because it is really important, my dear friends, that you have the background information you need to form your own opinions; I will now present you with some more external facts.

When we look at present-day Europe, with the exception of the eastern part inhabited by Slavs, we find that a large part of this Europe emerged from what is known as the empire of Charlemagne in the 8th and 9th centuries. This empire of Charlemagne—we will not characterize it further, nor will we take into account the fact that today the most diverse people argue about Charlemagne, because this argument about Charlemagne really makes almost as much sense as three sons arguing about their father, all three of whom have the right to call him their father. It is very often the case that three people would not argue about something if they did not have a common father, because then the object of the dispute would probably disappear – namely, the inheritance!

Three main areas emerged from the empire of Charlemagne: the western part, which after various vicissitudes became modern-day France; an eastern part, which essentially became modern-day Germany and Austria, with the exception of the Slavic and Magyar areas; and a central part, which essentially became modern-day Italy. Basically, all three parts have absolutely the same right to trace their origins back to Charlemagne. And sometimes it can even depend on strange feelings whether people want to trace their origins back to Charlemagne or not – if someone remembers how many Saxons Charlemagne had slaughtered, they might not attach any particular importance to tracing their origins back to Charlemagne! So these three areas emerged from the empire of Charlemagne. If we want to understand much of what is happening today, we must also bear in mind that throughout the Middle Ages there were certain relationships of an ideal nature between the actual central area and the eastern area – relationships such as those that exist today in this field, if one does not take certain phrases seriously, because what ultimately formed the basis of the Holy Roman Empire were, to a large extent, idealistic reasons. And anyone who does not want to believe that these were idealistic reasons should read Dante's writings on monarchy or otherwise inform themselves about the way Dante thought about these things. And let him consider that it was Dante who, for example, reproached Rudolf of Habsburg for caring too little about Italy, the “most beautiful garden of the empire.” Dante was—at least in the part of his life that matters most—an absolute supporter of that ideal community that had been established and was called Germany-Italy.

Now we see the Republic of Venice from the 13th and 14th centuries rebelling, as it were, against what came from the north. Venice did swallow up the Patriarchate of Aquileia, but above all, the Republic of Venice was keen to gain a firm foothold in the Adriatic, in the coastal regions of the Adriatic. Well, the Republic of Venice was very successful at that time, and we see how, in fact, what came from the north was pushed back under the influence of the Republic of Venice. Then came—I have discussed this here on another occasion—what is known as the Renaissance, which grew in Italy under the influence of the flourishing of the free cities. But then came the Counter-Reformation, the policy emanating from the papal-Spanish side. And we see that, basically, it was not until the 18th century that Italy was able to think about recovering from centuries of pain and suffering. And I do not need to explain here – it can be read in any history book – how the time then came when Italy found its unity to the applause of the whole world. And anyone familiar with the circumstances knows that nowhere more than in the German territories – well, perhaps one cannot say nowhere more, but in any case as much as anywhere else – was enthusiasm for Italian unity aroused.

But now the question may be raised: How did the modern unity of Italy come about? And this unification of Italy, my dear friends, must be taken as an example—as a particularly important example of how the unity of states comes about. On the other hand, we must learn to understand the connection between what I told you eight days ago or last Sunday about the events in Serbia and the events in Italy, for there are connections that are of immense importance for understanding the circumstances. But first we must consider a little how the structure of the Italian state, which is certainly to be recognized without envy, came about.

Isn't that so? One need only go back to the Battle of Solferino, where France stood on the side of Italy and where the first step was taken toward the later formation of the modern Italian state. So there we are in the 1850s. And we may ask ourselves: How was it possible back then—because the stakes were really very high—how was it possible back then? Read the history, and you will find that what I am telling you now is entirely true. How was it possible that the first step on the path to modern Italy was taken by Italy and France at Solferino? It was because Prussia and Austria—Austria had nothing to lose—could not unite! What happened later is thanks to the fact that Italy had a truly great statesman in Camillo Cavour, in whose soul the idea arose to achieve something in Italy, starting from this beginning, that could lead to a kind of revival of ancient Roman greatness. But things took a different course, and I would say something similar, albeit perhaps with a completely different tone, something similar to what we saw in the transition from the noble Serbian prince Michael Obrenovič to the later Serbian rulers, we find in the transition from the great soul of Camillo Cavour to the souls of the later statesmen—a transition, one might say, from idealism to a realism that was at first quite superficial. I can only sketch things out here.

Italy progressed from stage to stage. By the summer of 1871, Victor Emmanuel was able to move into Rome. What made this possible? The German victories over France! Francesco Crispi, a later Italian statesman, said it himself, for the following sentence comes from him: Italy went to Rome thanks to the German victories. France had given the initial impetus at Solferino, but it was the German victories over France that led to Rome becoming the capital of the Kingdom of Italy. And now a strange relationship developed between Italy and France. It is interesting to see how, as Italy consolidated its unity, it entered into a strange relationship with France: it became both an enemy and an ally. And now we must consider that Italy had statesmen who – and this is the plain truth – attached great importance to the fact that Italy had been brought together as a state from outside and that the last great step towards unity was actually thanks to Germany. These statesmen were there. They also saw that at that time a possible alliance with France could not be fruitful for Italy. But this current was contradicted by another — one that gradually emerged and grew strong, especially from 1876 onwards; this first current was contradicted by that of the Francophile democratic left-wing party. And now this state was swinging, so to speak, between its emotional inclination toward France and its more practical inclination toward Central Europe. But the strange thing was that in everything that was developing, the practical orientation toward Central Europe always prevailed—that was the reality.

Then a new turn came in the whole affair when France spread over to Tunis—Tunis had always been regarded as a place that naturally belonged to Italy. Now France began to spread there. And then the practical direction in Italy gained the upper hand – the direction that now leaned toward Central Europe. It is interesting, for example, that at the Berlin Congress, the Italian negotiator asked why Bismarck was offering France the opportunity to expand quietly in Africa, whether he really wanted to involve Italy in a war with France. In any case, Italy was dependent on Germany for the Italian statesmen of the time, and as Bismarck famously said, “The road to Germany leads through Vienna,” Italy was also dependent on Austria, which is why the old enmity had to be put aside, which Austria had taken on as its tragic fate, I would say. For with everything that the Republic of Venice had done, what had been pushed out of Italy had actually gone to Germany; Austria then had to take over the movement that came from the north. Under the influence of French actions in North Africa, the Francophile tendency had to take a back seat, and at that time, joining Central Europe became a matter of course for Italy.

You know that the Triple Alliance came into being—I am only mentioning these things in outline because it is not my job to engage in politics, but certain things need to be known, and unfortunately they are far too little known today—you know that in 1882 the so-called Triple Alliance came into being. And certain people will always judge this Triple Alliance wrongly because they cannot get used to applying valid terms to these things. There are actually people who, for example, attribute today's painful events of war to the Triple Alliance and not to the so-called Triple Entente, the “Entente cordiale” or whatever it is called. But you see, in such matters, valid terms are not always used; everywhere else, when something is supposed to lead to something, people ask whether it really does lead to it and how long it will be effective. Now, it has always been said of those who were involved in the Triple Alliance that it was created to preserve peace. And for many decades it served to preserve peace, that is, for decades it achieved what it was said to be intended to achieve. Then the Triple Entente was founded, which was also said to be “for the preservation of peace.” But it did not take a decade—and peace was gone! Every other thing in the world, my dear friends, would be judged by what it produces; but in these matters alone, we do not allow ourselves to make an objective judgment. After only five years, that secret plan was put into motion which makes it possible to study more closely the alchemy of those bullets and bombs which, as I told you recently in various contexts, were used in Sarajevo to carry out that assassination. For that assassination in June 1914 could hardly have failed – if some bullets missed, others would hit! At that time, ample precautions were taken to ensure that even if one thing failed, another would not. It was such a well-planned, one might say large-scale assassination attempt, the likes of which had never been seen before in world history. If one studies the alchemy of these bullets, so to speak, one comes to understand a little of these things, which we are now mentioning at the request of our friends. I will come back to this later.

After only five years, something was mixed into the entire tripartite alliance of Central Europe that can be described as follows: a certain connection was created between every event that took place in Italy and every event that took place in the Balkans. The aim was to ensure that nothing could happen in the Balkans without something corresponding happening in Italy. And the passions of the people were to interact in such a way that no unilateral action could ever take place here or there, but that feelings and thoughts would always be parallel. There was a close connection between the various impulses on the Apennine Peninsula and the Balkan Peninsula throughout the decades. Sometimes such a thing strikes one as immensely symbolic—symbolically beautiful, beautiful in relation to theory, just as a doctor calls a particularly serious case a “beautiful case” because it gives him the opportunity to perform a good operation, but this does not mean that the case is beautiful at all.

We were once in Italy and visited a man in Rome who was a very nice, kind person and a very friendly gentleman – he is now deceased. He led us into his salon, where we found two paintings by Draga Mašin and Alexander Obrenovič in a very prominent place, large and with dedications in the artists' own hand. This man was not only a very famous professor, but also one of the organizers of the so-called Latin League, [the “Lega Nazionale”], which was involved in the preparations for the separation of South Tyrol and Trieste from Austria and their annexation to Italy. Now, my dear friends, I do not, of course, want to draw any grand conclusions from such an insignificant experience, but I must say that it is symbolically significant that someone who organized a Latin League, who used this Latin League to revolutionize the students of the University of Innsbruck – I am not judging, I am not criticizing, I am simply recounting – that this man had pictures of Alexander Obrenovič and Draga Ma$in with their own handwritten dedications hanging in his salon, there, where everyone can see them, has pictures of Alexander Obrenovič and Draga Ma$in with dedications written in his own hand. Since this was at a time when I was well aware of the mysterious threads that exist between Rome and Belgrade, it made a certain symptomatic impression on me, because one is brought together with what is important to one in the world through one's karma, and if you are able to look at things in the right way and see through them, then you can already see that karma leads you to the place where you can “smell” what you need to “smell” for your own insight.

Now it so happened that in 1888 — it was one of those years that could just as easily have led to world war as 1914 — that in 1888, Crispi's adherence to the Triple Alliance prevented this crisis. This crisis was therefore prevented by Crispi, the Italian Prime Minister, remaining loyal to the Triple Alliance. But he remained loyal to the Triple Alliance only because France was advancing and expanding in North Africa. Now, France was pursuing a policy at that time which France itself said was intended to “reconquer Italy, which was beginning to turn away from France, through starvation,” that is, it was attempting to wage a kind of trade war against Italy—the famous trade war, which really played a major role at that time. The result of this trade war was that practical ties with Central Europe became ever closer. And perhaps I would do well not to quote any judgment from Germany, but rather the judgment of a Frenchman who said that modern Italy was an economic organization of Germany.

This means – as has often been emphasized, not only by Germans but also by others – that Italy was saved from the danger of being conquered by France through starvation, which is not exactly a pleasant prospect, by entering into closer economic relations with Germany. All of this combined to resolve the crisis at the end of the 1880s in a peaceful manner. It is extremely interesting to study the details of this crisis at the end of the 1880s, because studying these details is particularly useful for those who are inclined to look at connections and not be blinded by appearances. I have done this, and it is extremely interesting to do so. In 1888, events took place in response to which I did the following: I went and sketched out everything that happened in 1888, replacing “1888” with “1914.” It is the same, exactly the same, my dear friends! Just as in 1914, when the great press campaign inspired by Petersburg began and spread to Germany, so it was in 1888. Just as in 1914, when a conflict was to be provoked between Germany and Austria, so it was in 1888. In short, the details are the same. And it is interesting that I was able to read to various people a speech that was given back then in 1888, in which I simply replaced “1888” with “1914,” and everyone believed that what was said back then in 1888 referred to 1914! My dear friends, if such things are possible, then one cannot speak of coincidences, but one must speak of driving forces at work and of a system behind it.

Well, in 1888 the matter passed for the reasons I have given. But then the situation became even more difficult. The circumstances became particularly difficult because the whole relationship between the Apennine Peninsula and Central Europe really took on such a character—it is psychologically interesting, especially for spiritual researchers, to study these things—it really took on the character that Italy, political Italy, had to be treated like some ladies—forgive me, I only mean the hysterical ones. Incredible things developed, namely because more and more people in Europe came to believe and propagate the idea that Austria must be broken up. I am not criticizing these things, I am merely recounting them.

You can see for yourself how this opinion was propagated in Europe if you read publications such as those by Loiseau, Chéradame, and so on—books that deal extensively with how Austria will be divided in the near future. And opinions such as those of Loiseau and Chéradame were thrown into the fire that was smoldering down there in the south. It was really not easy to do what is often called politics under these circumstances, because, you see, in Italy, for example—I don't want to criticize this, I don't want to speak for or against it in the slightest, I just want to tell you—even the man who had planned an assassination attempt on Emperor Franz Joseph was celebrated. In contrast, in Vienna, in an exhibition that the Duke of the Abruzzi wanted to visit, a painting could not be called “The Battle of Lissa” – because Austria had won it – but was simply labeled “A Sea Battle” so that the Duke of the Abruzzi would not be offended when he came to Vienna to see the exhibition. But that is just one example of countless examples – and that is what was actually done. I am not criticizing this, but I am asking about reciprocity; I am asking whether anyone in Italy would have deigned to show such consideration by omitting the name of a won sea battle – in Vienna, however, this was done. One may even find this wrong from a certain point of view, but I am asking about reciprocity. And let this be said to characterize the mood a little, because such moods are important when a current such as that which came from the “Grand Orient de France” intervenes, when occult impulses are brought into play.

And, my dear friends, certain things that humanity has not cared about until now will have to become things that humanity cares about, because the “massoni” are not such that they do not see what is there, but they are intent—just like the other occult brotherhoods—on bringing the forces that are there into play. They know that impulses exist here and there and how to use them. And if, on the one hand, there is a certain current in the Apennines and another in the Balkans, then these currents must be used in the appropriate way, and then, at the right moment, that is, at the right moment for these people, one can do this or that.

This, then, is a preparation for the alchemical consideration I have spoken to you about, which will then take us a little further. I ask you to note that if I am to comply with the wishes of our friends, I cannot help but mention some of what is happening at present in connection with things that exist, even if not everyone agrees that such things should be brought to the surface. However, it is my conviction, my dear friends, that it is precisely because we close our eyes to these things and talk about what is happening from as unobjective a standpoint as possible that one of the main reasons why such painful things as are now happening can spread throughout the world, for even in the face of these great things, everyone should begin with self-knowledge. And a piece of self-knowledge is already this: knowing that the moment you say such things are none of your business, that you only want to hear about occult things, you are promoting, even if only in a small way at first, the development that, when joined together from many individual links [into a chain] and added up, leads to such things as we are experiencing today. For the occult is not only that which relates to the higher worlds—that is certainly occult for all human beings at first—but occult, my dear friends, is also, for many people, that which happens on the physical plane. And one would wish that some of the occult in this area would become apparent, because the fact that so much remains occult to so many who then judge is one of the sources of the misery we experience.

Tomorrow, if no one objects, we will meet again at five o'clock.

OSZAR »